Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Four-valued tables and modal logic.Richard L. Purtill - 1970 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 11 (4):505-511.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Inferences from Inconsistent Premises.Nicholas Rescher & Ruth Manor - 1970 - Theory and Decision 1 (2):179-217, 1970-1971.
    The main object of this paper is to provide the logical machinery needed for a viable basis for talking of the ‘consequences’, the ‘content’, or of ‘equivalences’ between inconsistent sets of premisses.With reference to its maximal consistent subsets (m.c.s.), two kinds of ‘consequences’ of a propositional set S are defined. A proposition P is a weak consequence (W-consequence) of S if it is a logical consequence of at least one m.c.s. of S, and P is an inevitable consequence (I-consequence) of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  • The Future of Logic: Foundation-Independence.Florian Rabe - 2016 - Logica Universalis 10 (1):1-20.
    Throughout the twentieth century, the automation of formal logics in computers has created unprecedented potential for practical applications of logic—most prominently the mechanical verification of mathematics and software. But the high cost of these applications makes them infeasible but for a few flagship projects, and even those are negligible compared to the ever-rising needs for verification. One of the biggest challenges in the future of logic will be to enable applications at much larger scales and simultaneously at much lower costs. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On rules of inference and the meanings of logical constants.Panu Raatikainen - 2008 - Analysis 68 (4):282-287.
    In the theory of meaning, it is common to contrast truth-conditional theories of meaning with theories which identify the meaning of an expression with its use. One rather exact version of the somewhat vague use-theoretic picture is the view that the standard rules of inference determine the meanings of logical constants. Often this idea also functions as a paradigm for more general use-theoretic approaches to meaning. In particular, the idea plays a key role in the anti-realist program of Dummett and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Two Dogmas of Empiricism.John G. Kemeny - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (4):281-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   216 citations  
  • On What There Is.Charles A. Baylis - 1954 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 19 (3):222-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • The logic of paradox.Graham Priest - 1979 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 8 (1):219 - 241.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   443 citations  
  • Tense-logic and the continuity of time.A. N. Prior - 1962 - Studia Logica 13 (1):133 - 151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Tense-Logic and the Continuity of Time.A. N. Prior & R. A. Bull - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):245-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Old Wine in (Somewhat Leaky) New Bottles: Some Comments on Beall.Graham Priest - 2016 - Australasian Journal of Logic 13 (5).
    Dialetheists concerning the paradoxes of self-refrence have often argued that the phenomeonon provides a choice between inconsistency and expressive incompleteness, and that inconsistency is the correct choice. In a recent paper 75: 573-84), JC Beall attacks this argument. This paper analyses his arguments, and argues that his paper simply provides a new spin on matters well known.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From Analogical Proportion to Logical Proportions.Henri Prade & Gilles Richard - 2013 - Logica Universalis 7 (4):441-505.
    Given a 4-tuple of Boolean variables (a, b, c, d), logical proportions are modeled by a pair of equivalences relating similarity indicators ( \({a \wedge b}\) and \({\overline{a} \wedge \overline{b}}\) ), or dissimilarity indicators ( \({a \wedge \overline{b}}\) and \({\overline{a} \wedge b}\) ) pertaining to the pair (a, b), to the ones associated with the pair (c, d). There are 120 semantically distinct logical proportions. One of them models the analogical proportion which corresponds to a statement of the form “a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Which Concepts Should We Use?: Metalinguistic Negotiations and The Methodology of Philosophy.David Plunkett - 2015 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 58 (7-8):828-874.
    This paper is about philosophical disputes where the literal content of what speakers communicate concerns such object-level issues as ground, supervenience, or real definition. It is tempting to think that such disputes straightforwardly express disagreements about these topics. In contrast to this, I suggest that, in many such cases, the disagreement that is expressed is actually one about which concepts should be employed. I make this case as follows. First, I look at non-philosophical, everyday disputes where a speaker employs a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   116 citations  
  • Splitting concepts.Gualtiero Piccinini & Sam Scott - 2006 - Philosophy of Science 73 (4):390-409.
    A common presupposition in the concepts literature is that concepts constitute a sin- gular natural kind. If, on the contrary, concepts split into more than one kind, this literature needs to be recast in terms of other kinds of mental representation. We offer two new arguments that concepts, in fact, divide into different kinds: (a) concepts split because different kinds of mental representation, processed independently, must be posited to explain different sets of relevant phenomena; (b) concepts split because different kinds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Synonymous logics.Francis Jeffry Pelletier & Alasdair Urquhart - 2003 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (3):259-285.
    This paper discusses the general problem of translation functions between logics, given in axiomatic form, and in particular, the problem of determining when two such logics are "synonymous" or "translationally equivalent." We discuss a proposed formal definition of translational equivalence, show why it is reasonable, and also discuss its relation to earlier definitions in the literature. We also give a simple criterion for showing that two modal logics are not translationally equivalent, and apply this to well-known examples. Some philosophical morals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Synonymous logics: A correction. [REVIEW]Francis Jeffry Pelletier & Alasdair Urquhart - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 37 (1):95 - 100.
    In an earlier paper entitled Synonymous Logics, the authors attempted to show that there are two modal logics so that each is exactly translatable into the other, but they are not translationally equivalent. Unfortunately, there is an error in the proof of this result. The present paper provides a new example of two such logics, and a proof of the result claimed in the earlier paper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How to say goodbye to the third man.Francis Jeffry Pelletier & Edward N. Zalta - 2000 - Noûs 34 (2):165–202.
    In (1991), Meinwald initiated a major change of direction in the study of Plato’s Parmenides and the Third Man Argument. On her conception of the Parmenides , Plato’s language systematically distinguishes two types or kinds of predication, namely, predications of the kind ‘x is F pros ta alla’ and ‘x is F pros heauto’. Intuitively speaking, the former is the common, everyday variety of predication, which holds when x is any object (perceptible object or Form) and F is a property (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Vagueness and utility: The semantics of common nouns. [REVIEW]Rohit Parikh - 1994 - Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (6):521 - 535.
    A utility-based approach to the understanding of vague predicates (VPs) is proposed. It is argued that assignment of truth values to propositions containing VPs entails unjustifiable assumptions of consensus; two models of VP semantics are criticized on this basis: (1) the super-truth theory of Kit Fine (1975), which requires an unlikely consensus on base points; (2) the fuzzy logic of Lotfi Zadeh (1975), on fuzzy truth values of sentences. Pragmatism is held to provide a key: successful behavior justifies a person's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • On the logic of the ontological argument.Paul E. Oppenheimer & Edward N. Zalta - 1991 - Philosophical Perspectives 5:509-529.
    In this paper, the authors show that there is a reading of St. Anselm's ontological argument in Proslogium II that is logically valid (the premises entail the conclusion). This reading takes Anselm's use of the definite description "that than which nothing greater can be conceived" seriously. Consider a first-order language and logic in which definite descriptions are genuine terms, and in which the quantified sentence "there is an x such that..." does not imply "x exists". Then, using an ordinary logic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • A Syntactic Approach to Closure Operation.Marek Nowak - 2017 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 46 (3/4).
    In the paper, tracing the traditional Hilbert-style syntactic account of logics, a syntactic characteristic of a closure operation defined on a complete lattice follows. The approach is based on observation that the role of rule of inference for a given consequence operation may be played by an ordinary binary relation on the complete lattice on which the closure operation is defined.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Towards a Practice-based Philosophy of Logic: Formal Languages as a Case Study.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2012 - Philosophia Scientiae 16:71-102.
    Au cours des dernières décennies, les travaux portant sur les pratiques humaines réelles ont pris de l'importance dans différents domaines de la philosophie, sans pour autant atteindre une position dominante. À ce jour, ce type de tournant pratique n'a cependant pas encore pénétré la philosophie de la logique. En première partie, j'esquisse ce que serait (ou pourrait être) une philosophie de la logique centrée sur l'étude des pratiques, en insistant en particulier sur sa pertinence et sur la manière de la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Towards a Practice-based Philosophy of Logic: Formal Languages as a Case Study.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2012 - Philosophia Scientiae 16 (1):71-102.
    Au cours des dernières décennies, les travaux portant sur les pratiques humaines réelles ont pris de l'importance dans différents domaines de la philosophie, sans pour autant atteindre une position dominante. À ce jour, ce type de tournant pratique n'a cependant pas encore pénétré la philosophie de la logique. En première partie, j'esquisse ce que serait (ou pourrait être) une philosophie de la logique centrée sur l'étude des pratiques, en insistant en particulier sur sa pertinence et sur la manière de la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Dynamics, Brandom-style.Bernhard Nickel - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 162 (2):333-354.
    Abstract This paper discusses the semantic theory presented in Robert Brandom’s Making It Explicit . I argue that it is best understood as a special version of dynamic semantics, so that these semantics by themselves offer an interesting theoretical alternative to more standard truth-conditional theories. This reorientation also has implications for more foundational issues. I argue that it gives us the resources for a renewed argument for the normativity of meaning. The paper ends by critically assessing the view in both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cracow Circle and Its Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics.Roman Murawski - 2015 - Axiomathes 25 (3):359-376.
    The paper is devoted to the presentation and analysis of the philosophical views concerning logic and mathematics of the leading members of Cracow Circle, i.e., of Jan Salamucha, Jan Franciszek Drewnowski and Józef Maria Bocheński. Their views on the problem of possible applicability of logical tools in metaphysical and theological researches is also discussed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Beyond Rasiowan Systems: Unital Deductive Systems.Alexei Y. Muravitsky - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (1):83-102.
    We deal with monotone structural deductive systems in an unspecified propositional language \ . These systems fall into several overlapping classes, forming a hierarchy. Along with well-known classes of deductive systems such as those of implicative, Fregean and equivalential systems, we consider new classes of unital and weakly implicative systems. The latter class is auxiliary, while the former is central in our discussion. Our analysis of unital systems leads to the concept of Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra which, under some natural conditions, is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • From inference to reasoning: The construction of rationality.David Moshman - 2004 - Thinking and Reasoning 10 (2):221 – 239.
    Inference is elementary and ubiquitous: Cognition always goes beyond the data. Thinking—including problem solving, decision making, judgement, planning, and argumentation—is here defined as the deliberate application and coordination of one's inferences to serve one's purposes. Reasoning, in turn, is epistemologically self-constrained thinking in which the application and coordination of inferences is guided by a metacognitive commitment to what are deemed to be justifiable inferential norms. The construction of rationality, in this view, involves increasing consciousness and control of logical and other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Was Lewis Carroll an Amazing Oppositional Geometer?Alessio Moretti - 2014 - History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (4):383-409.
    Some Carrollian posthumous manuscripts reveal, in addition to his famous ‘logical diagrams’, two mysterious ‘logical charts’. The first chart, a strange network making out of fourteen logical sentences a large 2D ‘triangle’ containing three smaller ones, has been shown equivalent—modulo the rediscovery of a fourth smaller triangle implicit in Carroll's global picture—to a 3D tetrahedron, the four triangular faces of which are the 3+1 Carrollian complex triangles. As it happens, such an until now very mysterious 3D logical shape—slightly deformed—has been (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Inconsistent mathematics.Chris Mortensen - 2008 - Studia Logica.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Book Reviews. [REVIEW]C. Mortensen - 2000 - Studia Logica 64 (2):285-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Conditionals, probability, and nontriviality.Charles G. Morgan & Edwin D. Mares - 1995 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (5):455-467.
    We show that the implicational fragment of intuitionism is the weakest logic with a non-trivial probabilistic semantics which satisfies the thesis that the probabilities of conditionals are conditional probabilities. We also show that several logics between intuitionism and classical logic also admit non-trivial probability functions which satisfy that thesis. On the other hand, we also prove that very weak assumptions concerning negation added to the core probability conditions with the restriction that probabilities of conditionals are conditional probabilities are sufficient to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Symmetric Categorial Grammar.Michael Moortgat - 2009 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 38 (6):681-710.
    The Lambek-Grishin calculus is a symmetric version of categorial grammar obtained by augmenting the standard inventory of type-forming operations (product and residual left and right division) with a dual family: coproduct, left and right difference. Interaction between these two families is provided by distributivity laws. These distributivity laws have pleasant invariance properties: stability of interpretations for the Curry-Howard derivational semantics, and structure-preservation at the syntactic end. The move to symmetry thus offers novel ways of reconciling the demands of natural language (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Multimodal linguistic inference.Michael Moortgat - 1996 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5 (3-4):349-385.
    In this paper we compare grammatical inference in the context of simple and of mixed Lambek systems. Simple Lambek systems are obtained by taking the logic of residuation for a family of multiplicative connectives /,,\, together with a package of structural postulates characterizing the resource management properties of the connective.Different choices for Associativity and Commutativity yield the familiar logics NL, L, NLP, LP. Semantically, a simple Lambek system is a unimodal logic: the connectives get a Kripke style interpretation in terms (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Multimodal Linguistic Inference.Michael Moortgat - 1995 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 3 (2-3):371-401.
    In this paper we compare grammatical inference in the context of simple and of mixed Lambek systems. Simple Lambek systems are obtained by taking the logic of residuation for a family of multiplicative connectives /, *, \, together with a package of structural postulates characterizing the resource management properties of the * connective. Different choices for Associativity and Commutativity yield the familiar logics NL, L, NLP, LP. Semantically, a simple Lambek system is a unimodal logic: the connectives get a Kripke (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Remarks on Descriptions and Natural Deduction.Richard Montague - 1957 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 3 (1-2):50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Remarks on Description and Natural Deduction.Richard Montague - 1957 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 3 (3-4):65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Classical relevant logics II.Robert K. Meyer & Richard Routley - 1974 - Studia Logica 33 (2):183 - 194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Classical relevant logics. I.R. K. Meyer & Richard Routley - 1973 - Studia Logica 32:51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Stability of nilpotent groups of class 2 and prime exponent.Alan H. Mekler - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):781-788.
    Let p be an odd prime. A method is described which given a structure M of finite similarity type produces a nilpotent group of class 2 and exponent p which is in the same stability class as M. Theorem. There are nilpotent groups of class 2 and exponent p in all stability classes. Theorem. The problem of characterizing a stability class is equivalent to characterizing the (nilpotent, class 2, exponent p) groups in that class.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Some Theorems About the Sentential Calculi of Lewis and Heyting.J. C. C. Mckinsey & Alfred Tarski - 1948 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (3):171-172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Some theorems about the sentential calculi of Lewis and Heyting.J. C. C. McKinsey & Alfred Tarski - 1948 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 13 (1):1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   145 citations  
  • Razonamiento aproximado y grados de consecuencia.Hubert Marraud - 1998 - Endoxa 1 (10):55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Data and phenomena in conceptual modelling.Benedikt Löwe & Thomas Müller - 2011 - Synthese 182 (1):131-148.
    The distinction between data and phenomena introduced by Bogen and Woodward (Philosophical Review 97(3):303–352, 1988) was meant to help accounting for scientific practice, especially in relation with scientific theory testing. Their article and the subsequent discussion is primarily viewed as internal to philosophy of science. We shall argue that the data/phenomena distinction can be used much more broadly in modelling processes in philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Pragma-Dialectics and the Function of Argumentation.Christoph Lumer - 2010 - Argumentation 24 (1):41-69.
    This contribution discusses some problems of Pragma-Dialectics and explains them by its consensualistic view of the function of argumentation and by its philosophical underpinnings. It is suggested that these problems can be overcome by relying on a better epistemology and on an epistemological theory of argumentation. On the one hand Pragma-Dialectics takes unqualified consensus as the aim of argumentation, which is problematic, (Sect. 2) on the other it includes strong epistemological and rationalistic elements (Sect. 3). The problematic philosophical underpinnings of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Zur Geschichte der Aussagenlogik.Jan Lukasiewicz - 1935 - Erkenntnis 5 (1):111-131.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Humean Supervenience Debugged.David Lewis - 1994 - Mind 103 (412):473--490.
    Tn this paper I explore and to an extent defend HS. The main philosophical challenges to HS come from philosophical views that say that nomic concepts-laws, chance, and causation-denote features of the world that fail to supervene on non-nomic features. Lewis rejects these views and has labored mightily to construct HS accounts of nomic concepts. His account of laws is fundamental to his program, since his accounts of the other nomic notions rely on it. Recently, a number of philosophers have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   605 citations  
  • The Solution to the Surprise Exam Paradox.Ken Levy - 2009 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 47 (2):131-158.
    The Surprise Exam Paradox continues to perplex and torment despite the many solutions that have been offered. This paper proposes to end the intrigue once and for all by refuting one of the central pillars of the Surprise Exam Paradox, the 'No Friday Argument,' which concludes that an exam given on the last day of the testing period cannot be a surprise. This refutation consists of three arguments, all of which are borrowed from the literature: the 'Unprojectible Announcement Argument,' the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Algebraic semantics for modal logics II.E. J. Lemmon - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (2):191-218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Algebraic semantics for modal logics I.E. J. Lemmon - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):46-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • What does a conditional knowledge base entail?Daniel Lehmann & Menachem Magidor - 1992 - Artificial Intelligence 55 (1):1-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  • Functional Semantics of Algebraic Theories.F. William Lawvere - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):340-341.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Lies and deception: an unhappy divorce.Jennifer Lackey - 2013 - Analysis 73 (2):236-248.
    The traditional view of lying holds that this phenomenon involves two central components: stating what one does not believe oneself and doing so with the intention to deceive. This view remained the generally accepted view of the nature of lying until very recently, with the intention-to-deceive requirement now coming under repeated attack. In this article, I argue that the tides have turned too quickly in the literature on lying. For while it is indeed true that there can be lies where (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations