Switch to: Citations

References in:

Deciding to Believe Again

Mind 116 (463):523 - 547 (2007)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Deciding to Believe Without Self-Deception.J. Thomas Cook - 1987 - Journal of Philosophy 84 (8):441-446.
    Williams, Elster and Pears hold that an effort to induce in oneself a belief in the truth of some proposition that one believes to be false can succeed only if one manages, somewhere along the way, to forget that one is engaged in such an effort. Although this view has strong intuitive appeal, it is false, and in this paper it is shown to be false by example.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • An Essay on Belief and Acceptance.Laurence Jonathan Cohen - 1992 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    In this incisive new book one of Britain's most eminent philosophers explores the often overlooked tension between voluntariness and involuntariness in human cognition. He seeks to counter the widespread tendency for analytic epistemology to be dominated by the concept of belief. Is scientific knowledge properly conceived as being embodied, at its best, in a passive feeling of belief or in an active policy of acceptance? Should a jury's verdict declare what its members involuntarily believe or what they voluntarily accept? And (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   259 citations  
  • Taking it to Heart.Jennifer Church - 2002 - The Monist 85 (3):361-380.
    We can assent to a proposition, build a theory around it, base our actions on it, and affirm its truth—without ever taking it to heart. This frequently happens, for example, to recipients of bad news who figure out what is entailed by the news, make appropriate plans, and pass the news on to others—all without really "taking it in." It happens to those who accept a scientific claim without abandoning their more private views of how things work, and it happens (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Why Is Belief Involuntary?Jonathan Bennett - 1990 - Analysis 50 (2):87 - 107.
    This paper will present a negative result—an account of my failure to explain why belief is involuntary. When I announced my question a year or so ahead of time, I had a vague idea of how it might be answered, but I cannot make it work out. Necessity, this time, has not given birth to invention. Still, my tussle with the question may contribute either towards getting it answered or showing that it cannot be answered because belief can be voluntary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Why is belief involuntary?Jonathan Bennett & Alonso Church - 1990 - Analysis 50 (2):87-107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Judgment and Justification.Lynne Rudder Baker - 1991 - Philosophical Review 100 (3):481.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Akratic believing?Jonathan E. Adler - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 110 (1):1 - 27.
    Davidson's account of weakness of will dependsupon a parallel that he draws between practicaland theoretical reasoning. I argue that theparallel generates a misleading picture oftheoretical reasoning. Once the misleadingpicture is corrected, I conclude that theattempt to model akratic belief on Davidson'saccount of akratic action cannot work. Thearguments that deny the possibility of akraticbelief also undermine, more generally, variousattempts to assimilate theoretical to practicalreasoning.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Change in View: Principles of Reasoning.Gilbert Harman - 1986 - Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press.
    Change in View offers an entirely original approach to the philosophical study of reasoning by identifying principles of reasoning with principles for revising one's beliefs and intentions and not with principles of logic. This crucial observation leads to a number of important and interesting consequences that impinge on psychology and artificial intelligence as well as on various branches of philosophy, from epistemology to ethics and action theory. Gilbert Harman is Professor of Philosophy at Princeton University. A Bradford Book.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   459 citations  
  • Judgement and justification.William G. Lycan - 1988 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Toward theory a homuncular of believing For years and years, philosophers took thoughts and beliefs to be modifications of incorporeal Cartesian egos. ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   307 citations  
  • Desiring To Believe.Grace Yee - 2002 - The Monist 85 (3):446-455.
    As a doxastic voluntarist, I am of the view that what I believe stems from what I want. This does not mean that I believe what I want when I want. It does not mean that in desiring to believe that p, I can bring about the belief that p—just like that. This is not what doxastic voluntarism is about. It must, however, be noted that this is the very conception opponents of the doctrine hold. Doxastic involuntarists maintain that voluntarism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Believing at will.Barbara Winters - 1979 - Journal of Philosophy 76 (5):243-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Williams, truth-aimedness and the voluntariness of judgement.Mark Thomas Walker - 2001 - Ratio 14 (1):68–83.
    I contend that while at least one of the arguments advanced by Bernard Williams in his paper ‘Deciding To Believe’ does establish that beliefs, or more precisely, judgements cannot be decided upon ‘at will’, the notion of truth‐aimedness presupposed by that argument also, ironically, provides the key to understanding why judgements are necessarily voluntary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The voluntariness of judgment.Mark Thomas Walker - 1996 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 39 (1):97 – 119.
    While various items closely associated with belief, such as speech?acts of assertion, or what have recently been termed acts of ?acceptance?, can clearly be voluntary, it is commonly supposed that belief itself, being intrinsically truth?directed, is essentially passive. I argue that while this may be true of belief proper, understood as a kind of disposition, it is not true of acts of assent or ?judgment?. Judgments, I contend, must be deemed voluntary precisely because of their truth?aimedness, for in their case (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Faith and reason.Richard Swinburne - 1981 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    "Faith and Reason is the final volume of a trilogy on philosophical theology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Faith and Reason.I. M. Crombie - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (134):76-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Faith and Reason.Richard Swinburne - 1981 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Richard Swinburne presents a new edition of the final volume of his acclaimed trilogy on philosophical theology. Faith and Reason is a self-standing examination of the implications for religious faith of Swinburne's famous arguments about the coherence of theism and the existence of God.By practising a particular religion, a person seeks to achieve some or all of three goals - that he worships and obeys God, gains salvation for himself, and helps others to attain their salvation. But not all religions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Clearing Space For Doxastic Voluntarism.Nishi Shah - 2002 - The Monist 85 (3):436-445.
    It is common for philosophers to claim that doxastic voluntarism, the view that an agent can form beliefs voluntarily, is false, and therefore that agents do not have the kind of control over their beliefs required for a straightforward application of deontological concepts such as obligation or duty in the domain of epistemology. The role that the denial of doxastic voluntarism plays in an argument to the effect that agents do not have obligations with respect to belief is simply this.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • On belief and the captivity of the will.Dion Scott-Kakures - 1994 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1):77-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Believing and willing.Louis P. Pojman - 1985 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 15 (March):37-56.
    It is widely held that we can obtain beliefs and withhold believing propositions directly by performing an act of will. This thesis is sometimes identified with the view that believing is a basic act, an act which is under our direct control. Descartes holds that the will is limitless in relation to belief acquisition and that we must be directly responsible for our beliefs, especially our false beliefs, for otherwise we could draw the blasphemous conclusion that God is responsible for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Epistemic Akrasia.David Owens - 2002 - The Monist 85 (3):381-397.
    One way of discerning what sort of control we have over our mental lives is to look at cases where that control is not exercised. This is one reason why philosophers have taken an interest in the phenomenon of akrasia, in an agent's ability to do, freely and deliberately, something that they judge they ought not to do. Akrasia constitutes a failure of control but not an absence of control. The akratic agent is not a compulsive; an akratic agent has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Believe what you want.Paul Noordhof - 2001 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 101 (3):247-265.
    The Uncontrollability Thesis is that it is metaphysically impossible consciously to believe that p at will. I review the standard ways in which this might be explained. They focus on the aim or purpose of belief being truth. I argue that these don't work. They either explain the aim in a way which makes it implausible that the Uncontrollability Thesis is true, or they fail to justify their claim that beliefs should be understood as aimed at the truth. I further (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • An Essay on Belief and Acceptance. [REVIEW]Joseph Moore - 1994 - Philosophical Review 103 (4):705.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • The Voluntariness of Belief.James Montmarquet - 1986 - Analysis 46 (1):49 - 53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Review of J udgement and Justification.Stephen Stich - 1993 - Noûs 27 (3):380-383.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Actions by Jennifer Hornsby. [REVIEW]Gary Watson - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (8):464-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Actions.Jennifer Hornsby - 1980 - Routledge and Kegan Paul.
    This book presents an events-based view of human action somewhat different from that of what is known as "standard story". A thesis about trying-to-do-something is distinguished from various volitionist theses. It is argued then that given a correct conception of action's antecedents, actions will be identified not with bodily movements but with causes of such movements.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Review of Gilbert Harman: Change in View: Principles of Reasoning[REVIEW]Howard Margolis - 1986 - Ethics 99 (4):966-966.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   253 citations  
  • The common mind: an essay on psychology, society, and politics.Philip Pettit - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    What makes human beings intentional and thinking subjects? How does their intentionality and thought connect with their social nature and their communal experience? How do the answers to these questions shape the assumptions which it is legitimate to make in social explanation and political evaluation? These are the broad-ranging issues which Pettit addresses in this novel study. The Common Mind argues for an original way of marking off thinking subjects, in particular human beings, from other intentional systems, natural and artificial. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   176 citations  
  • Language, belief, and metaphysics.Howard Evans Kiefer & Milton Karl Munitz (eds.) - 1970 - Albany,: State University of New York Press.
    Papers delivered at the International Philosophy Year conference at Brockport, 1967-68. Includes bibliographical references.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes.Peter Carruthers & Jill Boucher (eds.) - 1998 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    What is the place of language in human cognition? Do we sometimes think in natural language? Or is language for purposes of interpersonal communication only? Although these questions have been much debated in the past, they have almost dropped from sight in recent decades amongst those interested in the cognitive sciences. Language and Thought is intended to persuade such people to think again. It brings together essays by a distinguished interdisciplinary team of philosophers and psychologists, who discuss various ways in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Deciding to believe.Bernard Williams - 1973 - In Problems of the Self. Cambridge University Press. pp. 136--51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   342 citations  
  • Change in View: Principles of Reasoning, Cambridge, Mass.Gilbert Harman - 1986 - Behaviorism 16 (1):93-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   712 citations  
  • Natural language and virtual belief.Keith Frankish - 1998 - In Peter Carruthers & Jill Boucher (eds.), Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes. Cambridge University Press. pp. 248.
    This chapter outlines a new argument for the view that language has a cognitive role. I suggest that humans exhibit two distinct kinds of belief state, one passively formed, the other actively formed. I argue that actively formed beliefs (_virtual beliefs_, as I call them) can be identified with _premising policies_, and that forming them typically involves certain linguistic operations. I conclude that natural language has at least a limited cognitive role in the formation and manipulation of virtual beliefs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Will. A Dual Aspect Theory.B. O'shaughnessy - 1983 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 45 (3):497-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations