Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Proofs and computations.Helmut Schwichtenberg - 2012 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by S. S. Wainer.
    Driven by the question, 'What is the computational content of a (formal) proof?', this book studies fundamental interactions between proof theory and computability. It provides a unique self-contained text for advanced students and researchers in mathematical logic and computer science. Part I covers basic proof theory, computability and Gödel's theorems. Part II studies and classifies provable recursion in classical systems, from fragments of Peano arithmetic up to Π11-CA0. Ordinal analysis and the (Schwichtenberg-Wainer) subrecursive hierarchies play a central role and are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Combinatorial principles weaker than Ramsey's Theorem for pairs.Denis R. Hirschfeldt & Richard A. Shore - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (1):171-206.
    We investigate the complexity of various combinatorial theorems about linear and partial orders, from the points of view of computability theory and reverse mathematics. We focus in particular on the principles ADS (Ascending or Descending Sequence), which states that every infinite linear order has either an infinite descending sequence or an infinite ascending sequence, and CAC (Chain-AntiChain), which states that every infinite partial order has either an infinite chain or an infinite antichain. It is well-known that Ramsey's Theorem for pairs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • On the strength of Ramsey's theorem for pairs.Peter A. Cholak, Carl G. Jockusch & Theodore A. Slaman - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):1-55.
    We study the proof-theoretic strength and effective content of the infinite form of Ramsey's theorem for pairs. Let RT n k denote Ramsey's theorem for k-colorings of n-element sets, and let RT $^n_{ denote (∀ k)RT n k . Our main result on computability is: For any n ≥ 2 and any computable (recursive) k-coloring of the n-element sets of natural numbers, there is an infinite homogeneous set X with X'' ≤ T 0 (n) . Let IΣ n and BΣ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • On the strength of Ramsey's theorem for pairs.Peter A. Cholak, Carl G. Jockusch & Theodore A. Slaman - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (1):1-55.
    We study the proof–theoretic strength and effective content of the infinite form of Ramsey's theorem for pairs. Let RTkndenote Ramsey's theorem fork–colorings ofn–element sets, and let RT<∞ndenote (∀k)RTkn. Our main result on computability is: For anyn≥ 2 and any computable (recursive)k–coloring of then–element sets of natural numbers, there is an infinite homogeneous setXwithX″ ≤T0(n). LetIΣnandBΣndenote the Σninduction and bounding schemes, respectively. Adapting the casen= 2 of the above result (whereXis low2) to models of arithmetic enables us to show that RCA0+IΣ2+ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Reverse mathematics and well-ordering principles: A pilot study.Bahareh Afshari & Michael Rathjen - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 160 (3):231-237.
    The larger project broached here is to look at the generally sentence “if X is well-ordered then f is well-ordered”, where f is a standard proof-theoretic function from ordinals to ordinals. It has turned out that a statement of this form is often equivalent to the existence of countable coded ω-models for a particular theory Tf whose consistency can be proved by means of a cut elimination theorem in infinitary logic which crucially involves the function f. To illustrate this theme, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Computations in higher types.Johan Moldestad - 1977 - New York: Springer Verlag.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Non-standard analysis in ACA0 and Riemann mapping theorem.Keita Yokoyama - 2007 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 53 (2):132-146.
    This research is motivated by the program of reverse mathematics and non-standard arguments in second-order arithmetic. Within a weak subsystem of second-order arithmetic ACA0, we investigate some aspects of non-standard analysis related to sequential compactness. Then, using arguments of non-standard analysis, we show the equivalence of the Riemann mapping theorem and ACA0 over WKL0. (© 2007 WILEY-VCH Verlag GmbH & Co. KGaA, Weinheim).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Weak systems of determinacy and arithmetical quasi-inductive definitions.P. D. Welch - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):418 - 436.
    We locate winning strategies for various ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{3}^{0}$ -games in the L-hierarchy in order to prove the following: Theorem 1. KP+Σ₂-Comprehension $\vdash \exists \alpha L_{\alpha}\ models"\Sigma _{2}-{\bf KP}+\Sigma _{3}^{0}-\text{Determinacy}."$ Alternatively: ${\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}-{\mathrm{C}\mathrm{A}}_{0}\phantom{\rule{0ex}{0ex}}$ "there is a β-model of ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{3}^{1}-{\mathrm{C}\mathrm{A}}_{0}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}+\text{\hspace{0.17 em}}{\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{3}^{0}$ -Determinacy." The implication is not reversible. (The antecedent here may be replaced with ${\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}\left({\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}\right)-{\mathrm{C}\mathrm{A}}_{0}:\text{\hspace{0.17em}}{\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}$ instances of Comprehension with only ${\mathrm{\Pi }}_{3}^{1}$ -lightface definable parameters—or even weaker theories.) Theorem 2. KP +Δ₂-Comprehension +Σ₂-Replacement + ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{3}^{0}\phantom{\rule{0ex}{0ex}}$ -Determinacy. (Here AQI (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Weak axioms of determinacy and subsystems of analysis I: δ20 games.Kazuyuki Tanaka - 1990 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 36 (6):481-491.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Weak axioms of determinacy and subsystems of analysis I: δmath image games.Kazuyuki Tanaka - 1990 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 36 (6):481-491.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Weak axioms of determinacy and subsystems of analysis II.Kazuyuki Tanaka - 1991 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 52 (1-2):181-193.
    In [10], we have shown that the statement that all ∑ 1 1 partitions are Ramsey is deducible over ATR 0 from the axiom of ∑ 1 1 monotone inductive definition,but the reversal needs П 1 1 - CA 0 rather than ATR 0 . By contrast, we show in this paper that the statement that all ∑ 0 2 games are determinate is also deducible over ATR 0 from the axiom of ∑ 1 1 monotone inductive definition, but the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Forcing with tagged trees.John R. Steel - 1978 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 15 (1):55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • On the strength of könig's duality theorem for countable bipartite graphs.Stephen G. Simpson - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (1):113-123.
    Let CKDT be the assertion that for every countably infinite bipartite graph G, there exist a vertex covering C of G and a matching M in G such that C consists of exactly one vertex from each edge in M. (This is a theorem of Podewski and Steffens [12].) Let ATR0 be the subsystem of second-order arithmetic with arithmetical transfinite recursion and restricted induction. Let RCA0 be the subsystem of second-order arithmetic with recursive comprehension and restricted induction. We show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Linear Orderings.Joseph G. Rosenstein - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (4):1207-1209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   71 citations  
  • Theory of recursive functions and effective computability.Hartley Rogers - 1987 - Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   480 citations  
  • Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability.Hartley Rogers - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (1):141-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   594 citations  
  • Direct and local definitions of the Turing jump.Richard A. Shore - 2007 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 7 (2):229-262.
    We show that there are Π5 formulas in the language of the Turing degrees, [Formula: see text], with ≤, ∨ and ∧, that define the relations x″ ≤ y″, x″ = y″ and so {x ∈ L2 = x ≥ y|x″ = y″} in any jump ideal containing 0. There are also Σ6&Π6 and Π8 formulas that define the relations w = x″ and w = x', respectively, in any such ideal [Formula: see text]. In the language with just ≤ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Infinite games in the Cantor space and subsystems of second order arithmetic.Takako Nemoto, MedYahya Ould MedSalem & Kazuyuki Tanaka - 2007 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 53 (3):226-236.
    In this paper we study the determinacy strength of infinite games in the Cantor space and compare them with their counterparts in the Baire space. We show the following theorems:1. RCA0 ⊢ equation image-Det* ↔ equation image-Det* ↔ WKL0.2. RCA0 ⊢ 2-Det* ↔ ACA0.3. RCA0 ⊢ equation image-Det* ↔ equation image-Det* ↔ equation image-Det ↔ equation image-Det ↔ ATR0.4. For 1 < k < ω, RCA0 ⊢ k-Det* ↔ k –1-Det.5. RCA0 ⊢ equation image-Det* ↔ equation image-Det.Here, Det* stands for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Necessary use of [image] induction in a reversal.Itay Neeman - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):561 - 574.
    Jullien's indecomposability theorem (INDEC) states that if a scattered countable linear order is indecomposable, then it is either indecomposable to the left, or indecomposable to the right. The theorem was shown by Montalbán to be a theorem of hyperarithmetic analysis, and then, in the base system RCA₀ plus ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}\text{\hspace{0.17em}}$ induction, it was shown by Neeman to have strength strictly between weak ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ choice and ${\mathrm{\Delta }}_{1}^{1}$ comprehension. We prove in this paper that ${\mathrm{\Sigma }}_{1}^{1}$ induction is needed for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reverse mathematics and π21 comprehension.Carl Mummert & Stephen G. Simpson - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):526-533.
    We initiate the reverse mathematics of general topology. We show that a certain metrization theorem is equivalent to Π2 1 comprehension. An MF space is defined to be a topological space of the form MF(P) with the topology generated by $\lbrace N_p \mid p \in P \rbrace$ . Here P is a poset, MF(P) is the set of maximal filters on P, and $N_p = \lbrace F \in MF(P) \mid p \in F \rbrace$ . If the poset P is countable, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Reverse Mathematics and Π 1 2 Comprehension.Carl Mummert & Stephen G. Simpson - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (3):526-533.
    We initiate the reverse mathematics of general topology. We show that a certain metrization theorem is equivalent to Π12 comprehension. An MF space is defined to be a topological space of the form MF with the topology generated by {Np ∣ p ϵ P}. Here P is a poset, MF is the set of maximal filters on P, and Np = {F ϵ MF ∣ p ϵ F }. If the poset P is countable, the space MF is said to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Indecomposable linear orderings and hyperarithmetic analysis.Antonio Montalbán - 2006 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 6 (1):89-120.
    A statement of hyperarithmetic analysis is a sentence of second order arithmetic S such that for every Y⊆ω, the minimum ω-model containing Y of RCA0 + S is HYP, the ω-model consisting of the sets hyperarithmetic in Y. We provide an example of a mathematical theorem which is a statement of hyperarithmetic analysis. This statement, that we call INDEC, is due to Jullien [13]. To the author's knowledge, no other already published, purely mathematical statement has been found with this property (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • [image] -Determinacy, Comprehension and Induction.Medyahya Ould Medsalem & Kazuyuki Tanaka - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (2):452 - 462.
    We show that each of $\Delta _{3}^{1}-{\rm CA}_{0}+\Sigma _{3}^{1}-{\rm IND}$ and $\Pi _{2}^{1}-{\rm CA}_{0}+\Pi _{3}^{1}-{\rm TI}$ proves $\Delta _{3}^{0}-{\rm Det}$ and that neither $\Sigma _{3}^{1}-{\rm IND}$ nor $\Pi _{3}^{1}-{\rm TI}$ can be dropped. We also show that neither $\Delta _{3}^{1}-{\rm CA}_{0}+\Sigma _{\infty}^{1}-{\rm IND}$ nor $\Pi _{2}^{1}-{\rm CA}_{0}+\Pi _{\infty}^{1}-{\rm TI}$ proves $\Sigma _{3}^{0}-{\rm Det}$. Moreover, we prove that none of $\Delta _{2}^{1}-{\rm CA}_{0}$, $\Sigma _{3}^{1}-{\rm IND}$ and $\Pi _{2}^{1}-{\rm TI}$ is provable in $\Delta _{1}^{1}-{\rm Det}_{0}={\rm ACA}_{0}+\Delta _{1}^{1}-{\rm Det}$.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Δ 0 3 -determinacy, comprehension and induction.MedYahya Ould MedSalem & Kazuyuki Tanaka - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (2):452-462.
    We show that each of Δ13-CA0 + Σ13-IND and Π12-CA0 + Π13-TI proves Δ03-Det and that neither Σ31-IND nor Π13-TI can be dropped. We also show that neither Δ13-CA0 + Σ1∞-IND nor Π12-CA0 + Π1∞-TI proves Σ03-Det. Moreover, we prove that none of Δ21-CA0, Σ31-IND and Π21-TI is provable in Δ11-Det0 = ACA0 + Δ11-Det.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The veblen functions for computability theorists.Alberto Marcone & Antonio Montalbán - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):575 - 602.
    We study the computability-theoretic complexity and proof-theoretic strength of the following statements: (1) "If X is a well-ordering, then so is ε X ", and (2) "If X is a well-ordering, then so is φ(α, X)", where α is a fixed computable ordinal and φ represents the two-placed Veblen function. For the former statement, we show that ω iterations of the Turing jump are necessary in the proof and that the statement is equivalent to ${\mathrm{A}\mathrm{C}\mathrm{A}}_{0}^{+}$ over RCA₀. To prove the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On Fraïssé’s conjecture for linear orders of finite Hausdorff rank.Alberto Marcone & Antonio Montalbán - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 160 (3):355-367.
    We prove that the maximal order type of the wqo of linear orders of finite Hausdorff rank under embeddability is φ2, the first fixed point of the ε-function. We then show that Fraïssé’s conjecture restricted to linear orders of finite Hausdorff rank is provable in +“φ2 is well-ordered” and, over , implies +“φ2 is well-ordered”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • On suborderings of the alpha-recursively enumerable alpha-degrees.Manuel Lerman - 1972 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 4 (4):369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Nonstandard arithmetic and reverse mathematics.H. Jerome Keisler - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (1):100-125.
    We show that each of the five basic theories of second order arithmetic that play a central role in reverse mathematics has a natural counterpart in the language of nonstandard arithmetic. In the earlier paper [3] we introduced saturation principles in nonstandard arithmetic which are equivalent in strength to strong choice axioms in second order arithmetic. This paper studies principles which are equivalent in strength to weaker theories in second order arithmetic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Nonstandard arithmetic and recursive comprehension.H. Keisler - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (8):1047-1062.
    First order reasoning about hyperintegers can prove things about sets of integers. In the author’s paper Nonstandard Arithmetic and Reverse Mathematics, Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 100–125, it was shown that each of the “big five” theories in reverse mathematics, including the base theory, has a natural nonstandard counterpart. But the counterpart of has a defect: it does not imply the Standard Part Principle that a set exists if and only if it is coded by a hyperinteger. In this paper (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The strength of Jullien's indecomposability theorem.Itay Neeman - 2008 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 8 (1):93-119.
    Jullien's indecomposability theorem states that if a scattered countable linear order is indecomposable, then it is either indecomposable to the left, or indecomposable to the right. The theorem was shown by Montalbán to be a theorem of hyperarithmetic analysis. We identify the strength of the theorem relative to standard reverse mathematics markers. We show that it lies strictly between weak [Formula: see text] choice and [Formula: see text] comprehension.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Higher set theory and mathematical practice.Harvey M. Friedman - 1971 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 2 (3):325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • General recursion theory: an axiomatic approach.Jens Erik Fenstad - 1980 - New York: Springer Verlag.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The polarized Ramsey’s theorem.Damir D. Dzhafarov & Jeffry L. Hirst - 2009 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 48 (2):141-157.
    We study the effective and proof-theoretic content of the polarized Ramsey’s theorem, a variant of Ramsey’s theorem obtained by relaxing the definition of homogeneous set. Our investigation yields a new characterization of Ramsey’s theorem in all exponents, and produces several combinatorial principles which, modulo bounding for ${\Sigma^0_2}$ formulas, lie (possibly not strictly) between Ramsey’s theorem for pairs and the stable Ramsey’s theorem for pairs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A Δ20 set with no infinite low subset in either it or its complement.Rod Downey, Denis R. Hirschfeldt, Steffen Lempp & Reed Solomon - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1371-1381.
    We construct the set of the title, answering a question of Cholak, Jockusch, and Slaman [1], and discuss its connections with the study of the proof-theoretic strength and effective content of versions of Ramsey's Theorem. In particular, our result implies that every ω-model of RCA 0 + SRT 2 2 must contain a nonlow set.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • A $\delta^0_2$ Set With No Infinite Low Subset In Either It Or Its Complement.Rod Downey, Denis Hirschfeldt, Steffen Lempp & Reed Solomon - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (3):1371-1381.
    We construct the set of the title, answering a question of Cholak, Jockusch, and Slaman [1], and discuss its connections with the study of the proof-theoretic strength and effective content of versions of Ramsey's Theorem. In particular, our result implies that every $\omega$-model of RCA$_0$+ SRT$^2_2$ must contain a nonlow set.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • [Omnibus Review].H. Jerome Keisler - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (2):342-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Reverse mathematics and well-ordering principles.Michael Rathjen & Andreas Weiermann - 2011 - In S. B. Cooper & Andrea Sorbi (eds.), Computability in Context: Computation and Logic in the Real World. World Scientific.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations