Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Scenes and other situations.Jon Barwise - 1981 - Journal of Philosophy 78 (7):369-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   68 citations  
  • Mental Events.Donald Davidson - 1970 - In Essays on Actions and Events: Philosophical Essays Volume 1. Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press. pp. 207-224.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   760 citations  
  • Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology.Jerry A. Fodor - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):63-73.
    The paper explores the distinction between two doctrines, both of which inform theory construction in much of modern cognitive psychology: the representational theory of mind and the computational theory of mind. According to the former, propositional attitudes are to be construed as relations that organisms bear to mental representations. According to the latter, mental processes have access only to formal (nonsemantic) properties of the mental representations over which they are defined.The following claims are defended: (1) That the traditional dispute between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   668 citations  
  • Categories, life, and thinking.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):269-283.
    Classifying is a fundamental operation in the acquisition of knowledge. Taxonomic theory can help students of cognition, evolutionary psychology, ethology, anatomy, and sociobiology to avoid serious mistakes, both practical and theoretical. More positively, it helps in generating hypotheses useful to a wide range of disciplines. Composite wholes, such as species and societies, are “individuals” in the logical sense, and should not be treated as if they were classes. A group of analogous features is a natural kind, but a group of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   185 citations  
  • Natural kinds.Willard V. Quine - 1969 - In Willard van Orman Quine (ed.), Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. Columbia University Press. pp. 114-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   169 citations  
  • The deception of the senses.Frederick J. E. Woodbridge - 1913 - Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 10 (1):5-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Quine on natural kinds.Hugh T. Wilder - 1972 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):263 – 270.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Property designation and description.N. L. Wilson - 1955 - Philosophical Review 64 (3):389-404.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Maxwell's Condition—Goodman's Problem.Mark Wilson - 1979 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (2):107-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A stroll through the worlds of animals and men: A picture book of invisible worlds.Jakob von Uexküll - 1992 - Semiotica 89 (4):319-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • Characteristics of projectible predicates.John M. Vickers - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (9):280-286.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Individualistic classes.Leigh van Valen - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (4):539-541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Individualistic Classes.Leigh Valevann - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (4):539-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Against direct perception.Shimon Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):333-81.
    Central to contemporary cognitive science is the notion that mental processes involve computations defined over internal representations. This view stands in sharp contrast to the to visual perception and cognition, whose most prominent proponent has been J.J. Gibson. In the direct theory, perception does not involve computations of any sort; it is the result of the direct pickup of available information. The publication of Gibson's recent book (Gibson 1979) offers an opportunity to examine his approach, and, more generally, to contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • The thesis of the efference-mediation of vision cannot be rationalized.M. T. Turvey - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):81-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Conflicting concepts of confirmation.Howard Smokler - 1968 - Journal of Philosophy 65 (10):300-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Abstract machine theory and direct perception.Robert Shaw & James Todd - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):400-401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The intentionality of intention and action.John R. Searle - 1979 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 22 (1-4):253 – 280.
    This article presents a sketch of a theory of action. It does so by locating the relation of intention to action -vithin a general theory of Intentionality. It introduces a distinction between ptiorintentions and intentions in actions; the concept of the experience of acting; and the thesis that both prior intentions and intentions in action are causally self-referential. Each of these is independently motivated, but together they allow suggested solutions to several outstanding problems within action theory (deviant causal chains, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • The Intentionality of Intention and Action.John R. Searle - 1980 - Cognitive Science 4 (1):47-70.
    Cognitive Science is likely to make little progress in the study of human behavior until we have a clear account of what a human action is. The aim of this paper is to present a sketch of a theory of action. I will locate the relation of intention to action within a general theory of Intentionality. I will introduce a distinction between prior intentions and intentions in actions; the concept of the experience of acting; and the thesis that both prior (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Information pickup is the activity of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):397-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How direct is visual perception?: Some reflections on Gibson's “ecological approach”.J. A. Fodor & Z. W. Pylyshyn - 1981 - Cognition 9 (2):139-196.
    Establishment holds that thc psychological mechanism of inference is the ment psychological thcorizing. Moreover, given this conciliatory reading, transformation of mental representations, it follows that perception is in.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  • Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundation of cognitive science.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):111-32.
    The computational view of mind rests on certain intuitions regarding the fundamental similarity between computation and cognition. We examine some of these intuitions and suggest that they derive from the fact that computers and human organisms are both physical systems whose behavior is correctly described as being governed by rules acting on symbolic representations. Some of the implications of this view are discussed. It is suggested that a fundamental hypothesis of this approach is that there is a natural domain of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   663 citations  
  • Is semantics possible?Hilary Putnam - 1970 - Metaphilosophy 1 (3):187–201.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Gruesome simplicity.Graham Priest - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (3):432-437.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Animal-environment mutuality and direct perception.Sandra S. Prindle, Claudia Carello & M. T. Turvey - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):395-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Dretske on laws of nature.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (3):431-439.
    In a recent article [4], Fred I. Dretske has proposed a new analysis of natural laws. Dretske rejects the more or less standard view which says that laws are universal truths with a special function or status in science. As an alternative account, he suggests that laws are expressed by singular statements describing the relationship between universal properties and magnitudes: the statement It is a law that F's are G's3.is to be analysed as F-ness ↦ G-ness.I shall argue, however, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • On projecting grue.John Moreland - 1976 - Philosophy of Science 43 (3):363-377.
    This paper attempts to place Goodman's "New Riddle of Induction" within the context of a subjectivist understanding of inductive logic. It will be argued that predicates such as 'grue' cannot be denied projectible status in any a priori way, but must be considered in the context of a situation of inductive support. In particular, it will be argued that questions of projectibility are to be understood as a variety of questions about the ways a given sample is random. Various examples (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Meaning and scientific status of causality.Henry Margenau - 1934 - Philosophy of Science 1 (2):133-148.
    The disagreement with regard to the validity of the principle of causality, existing to-day among scientists, has its roots in the diversity of definitions of the principle itself rather than in a problematic scientific situation. As far as the formulation of quantum theory is complete its bearing upon philosophical questions can be fixed with precision provided the questions are phrased intelligibly. But a question is intelligible from a scientific point of view only if it satisfies two conditions: the meaning of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Biological species as natural kinds.David B. Kitts & David J. Kitts - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (4):613-622.
    The fact that the names of biological species refer independently of identifying descriptions does not support the view of Ghiselin and Hull that species are individuals. Species may be regarded as natural kinds whose members share an essence which distinguishes them from the members of other species and accounts for the fact that they are reproductively isolated from the members of other species. Because evolutionary theory requires that species be spatiotemporally localized their names cannot occur in scientific laws. If natural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • A matter of individuality.David L. Hull - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (3):335-360.
    Biological species have been treated traditionally as spatiotemporally unrestricted classes. If they are to perform the function which they do in the evolutionary process, they must be spatiotemporally localized individuals, historical entities. Reinterpreting biological species as historical entities solves several important anomalies in biology, in philosophy of biology, and within philosophy itself. It also has important implications for any attempt to present an "evolutionary" analysis of science and for sciences such as anthropology which are devoted to the study of single (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   396 citations  
  • Studies in the logic of explanation.Carl Gustav Hempel & Paul Oppenheim - 1948 - Philosophy of Science 15 (2):135-175.
    To explain the phenomena in the world of our experience, to answer the question “why?” rather than only the question “what?”, is one of the foremost objectives of all rational inquiry; and especially, scientific research in its various branches strives to go beyond a mere description of its subject matter by providing an explanation of the phenomena it investigates. While there is rather general agreement about this chief objective of science, there exists considerable difference of opinion as to the function (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   700 citations  
  • The inference to the best explanation.Gilbert H. Harman - 1965 - Philosophical Review 74 (1):88-95.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   518 citations  
  • Powers.R. Harré - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (1):81-101.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The problem of counterfactual conditionals.Nelson Goodman - 1947 - Journal of Philosophy 44 (5):113-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   175 citations  
  • What gives rise to the perception of motion?James J. Gibson - 1968 - Psychological Review 75 (4):335-346.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • How direct is visual perception? Some reflections on Gibson's 'ecological approach'.Jerry A. Fodor & Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1981 - Cognition 9 (2):139-96.
    Examines the theses that the postulation of mental processing is unnecessary to account for our perceptual relationship with the world, see turvey etal. for a criticque.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   289 citations  
  • Interpretation of imperfect line data as a three-dimensional scene.Gilbert Falk - 1972 - Artificial Intelligence 3:101-144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The very thought of grue.Haskell Fain - 1967 - Philosophical Review 76 (1):61-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The universality of laws.John Earman - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (2):173-181.
    Various senses in which laws of nature are supposed to be "universal" are distinguished. Conditions designed to capture the content of the more important of these senses are proposed and the relations among these conditions are examined. The status of universality requirements is briefly discussed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Reply to Niiniluoto.Fred I. Dretske - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (3):440-444.
    In “Laws of Nature” [1] I argued that natural laws are not universal truths. Laws have properties that enable them to function in a special way. Since universal truths do not have these properties, they cannot be promoted to the status of laws by assigning them this function, by using them in the way laws are typically used. To suppose that we could effect this transformation by the way we used a generalization is like supposing that we could make thumb (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Laws of nature.Fred I. Dretske - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (2):248-268.
    It is a traditional empiricist doctrine that natural laws are universal truths. In order to overcome the obvious difficulties with this equation most empiricists qualify it by proposing to equate laws with universal truths that play a certain role, or have a certain function, within the larger scientific enterprise. This view is examined in detail and rejected; it fails to account for a variety of features that laws are acknowledged to have. An alternative view is advanced in which laws are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   439 citations  
  • Are Species Really Individuals?David L. Hull - 1976 - Systematic Zoology 25:174–191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   215 citations  
  • A Radical Solution to the Species Problem.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1974 - Systematic Zoology 23 (4):536–544.
    Traditionally, species have been treated as classes. In fact they may be considered individuals. The logical term “individual” has been confused with a biological synonym for “organism.” If species are individuals, then: 1) their names are proper, 2) there cannot be instances of them, 3) they do not have defining properties, 4) their constituent organisms are parts, not members. “ Species " may be defined as the most extensive units in the natural economy such that reproductive competition occurs among their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   294 citations  
  • Belief and disposition.Isaac Levi & Sidney Morgenbesser - 1964 - American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (3):221-232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Knowledge, Inference, and Explanation.Gilbert Harman - 1968 - American Philosophical Quarterly 5 (3):164 - 173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   72 citations  
  • Underlying trait terms.William K. Goosens - 1977 - In Stephen P. Schwartz (ed.), Naming, Necessity, and Natural Kinds. Cornell University Press. pp. 13--41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What is a Law of Nature?A. J. Ayer - 1956 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 10 (2=36):144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • The primacy of perceiving.M. T. Turvey & R. Show - 1979 - In L. Nilsson (ed.), Perspectives on Memory Research. pp. 367--372.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations