Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Psychophysiological Transcendentalism in Friedrich Albert Lange’s Social and Political Philosophy.Elisabeth Theresia Widmer - 2022 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 3 (1):253-275.
    In recent literature, it has been suggested that Lange’s social and political philosophy is separate from his neo-Kantian program. Prima facie, this interpretation makes sense given that Lange argues for an account of social norms that builds on Darwin and Smith rather than on Kant. Still, this paper argues that elements of psychophysiological transcendentalism can be found in Lange’s social and political philosophy. A detailed examination of the second edition of the History of Materialism, Schiller’s Poems, and the second edition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • ONTOLOGIA E CIÊNCIA NA CRÍTICA DE NIETZSCHE À METAFÍSICA EM HUMANO, DEMASIADO HUMANO.William Mattioli - 2020 - Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 145 (145):231-259.
    RESUMO Neste artigo, discuto o que considero serem os pressupostos ontológicos da crítica de Nietzsche à metafísica no primeiro livro de Humano, demasiado humano e a natureza da relação estabelecida por ele entre filosofia e ciência. Busco definir sua posição como um realismo científico moderado, que considera que as ciências caminham progressivamente em direção a uma concepção puramente dinâmica do real. ABSTRACT In this paper I discuss what I consider to be the ontological assumptions of Nietzsche’s critique of metaphysics in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bürgerliche intelligenz.Robert M. Brain - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 26 (4):617-635.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Studying Kanonbildung: An Exercise in a Distant Reading of Contemporary Self-descriptions of the 19th Century German Philosophy.Maxim Demin & Alexei Kouprianov - 2018 - Social Epistemology 32 (2):112-127.
    In 19th century Germany, the number of publications in the history of philosophy increased dramatically. According to Ulrich Schneider’s calculations, from 1810 through 1899, 148 original textbooks by 114 authors were published in German. The aim of this article is to analyse how the documented in these publications canonic vision of 19th century German philosophy evolved. An analysis of 66 treatises published from 1802 through 1918 allows dividing 19th century philosophers into groups based on the frequency of their names across (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle in Prussian Gymnasiums: Why the Texts of the Ancient Philosopher Became Popular for Teaching Logic.Maxim Demin - 2019 - History and Philosophy of Logic 40 (4):374-388.
    During the nineteenth century, German philosophy developed from a type of general knowledge to an academic discipline at the university. Changes across disciplines to the philosophy of science and psychological surveys created new challenges for the place and purpose of philosophy in the educational system. The content of logic courses for secondary schools (Gymnasiums) was centred on the dissociation of nature and the scale of logic. In this paper, I will examine a number of projects for teaching philosophy at the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Elisabeth Theresia Widmer: Left-Kantianism in the Marburg School[REVIEW]Sabato Danzilli - 2024 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 5 (1):75-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Elisabeth Theresia Widmer: Left-Kantianism in the Marburg School. [REVIEW]Sabato Danzilli - 2024 - Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 5 (1):75-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wilhelm diltheys empirische philosophie und der rezente methodenstreit in der analytischen philosophie.Christian Damböck - 2012 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 85 (1):151-185.
    Wilhelm Dilthey's epistemology is an attempt at a more cogent and non-reductionist version of empiricism. According to Dilthey the concepts and ideas of the human mind are empirical objects in their own right. Thus, philosophy as the study of these “facts of consciousness” turns out to be an empirical science; its methods are the methods of psychology, sociology, and history. These views of Dilthey are firstly described in the context of their competitive philosophical programs—“metaphysics”, empiricism and -Kantianism—, then they are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Rudolf Carnap and Wilhelm Dilthey:“German” Empiricism in the Aufbau.Christian Damböck - 2012 - In R. Creath (ed.), Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook. Springer Verlag. pp. 67--88.
    Rudolf Carnap’s formative years as a philosopher were his time in Jena where he studied mathematics, physics, and philosophy, among others, with Gottlob Frege, the neo-Kantian Bruno Bauch, and Herman Nohl, a pupil of Wilhelm Dilthey.2 Whereas both the influence of Frege and of the neo-Kantians is quite well known,3 the importance of the Dilthey school for Carnap’s intellectual development was recently highlighted by scholars, such as Gottfried Gabriel and Hans-Joachim Dahms.4 Although Carnap himself was interested mainly in the problems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Psychoanalyse und Neukantianismus.Brandon Bloch - 2022 - Psyche 76 (2):139-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What Does It Mean That “Space Can Be Transcendental Without the Axioms Being So”?: Helmholtz’s Claim in Context.Francesca Biagioli - 2014 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 45 (1):1-21.
    In 1870, Hermann von Helmholtz criticized the Kantian conception of geometrical axioms as a priori synthetic judgments grounded in spatial intuition. However, during his dispute with Albrecht Krause (Kant und Helmholtz über den Ursprung und die Bedeutung der Raumanschauung und der geometrischen Axiome. Lahr, Schauenburg, 1878), Helmholtz maintained that space can be transcendental without the axioms being so. In this paper, I will analyze Helmholtz’s claim in connection with his theory of measurement. Helmholtz uses a Kantian argument that can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The misadventures of the “problem” in “philosophy”: From Kant to Deleuze.Giuseppe Bianco - 2018 - Angelaki 23 (2):8-30.
    Notwithstanding the recent prominence of the term “problem” in the humanities, few scholars have analysed its history. This essay tries to partially fill that lack, principally covering the period from late modernity through to the 1960s, in order to understand the role that the term plays in “Continental” philosophy, with special emphasis on the writings of Gilles Deleuze. This analysis focuses on the strategies employed by different agents to define “philosophical” problems, or “philosophical” ways of posing problems. The term, originally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • El derecho a la autoconservación en la existencia en la filosofía Del derecho de Johann G. Fichte Y en la ética de Hermann Cohen.Héctor Oscar Arrese Igor - 2009 - Revista de filosofía (Chile) 65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gibt es eine österreichische Psychologie?Mauro Antonelli - 2022 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 99 (2):248-272.
    This article, inspired by Rudolf Haller’s thesis of an independent, specific, and unitary Austrian tradition of scientific philosophy, develops the idea of a specific Austrian tradition of psychological research, as distinguished in its development from that in Germany. This tradition was shaped by two phenomenological trends, which were merged into unity in Prague by Carl Stumpf and Brentano’s students of the second generation. One trend traces back to Goethe and was continued in Prague by the physiologists Jan E. Purkinje and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Jean van Heijenoort’s Conception of Modern Logic, in Historical Perspective.Irving H. Anellis - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (3):339-409.
    I use van Heijenoort’s published writings and manuscript materials to provide a comprehensive overview of his conception of modern logic as a first-order functional calculus and of the historical developments which led to this conception of mathematical logic, its defining characteristics, and in particular to provide an integral account, from his most important publications as well as his unpublished notes and scattered shorter historico-philosophical articles, of how and why the mathematical logic, whose he traced to Frege and the culmination of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neo-Kantianism and the Roots of Anti-Psychologism.R. Lanier Anderson - 2005 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 13 (2):287-323.
    This paper explores a pair of puzzling and controversial topics in the history of late nineteenth-century philosophy: the psychologism debates, and the nature of neo-Kantianism. Each is sufficientl...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • De la filosofía trascendental a la ontología fundamental. Heidegger descubre a Kant.Bernardo Ainbinder - 2011 - Studia Heideggeriana 1:5-12.
    En este artículo introductorio, exploro el sentido de la influencia de Kant en la filosofía de Heidegger, y en particular examino el significado de su afirmación tardía según la cual "la ontología fundamental no es otra cosa que filosofía trascendental". Sostengo que, para dar sentido a esta afirmación, no tendremos que limitarnos a la lectura atenta de Heidegger sobre Kant a finales de la década de 1920, sino que nos centraremos en sus primeros trabajos sobre lógica y en su redescubrimiento (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hermann Cohen and Kant's Concept of Experience.Nicholas F. Stang - 2018 - In Christian Damböck (ed.), Philosophie und Wissenschaft bei Hermann Cohen. Springer. pp. 13–40.
    In this essay I offer a partial rehabilitation of Cohen’s Kant interpretation. In particular, I will focus on the center of Cohen’s interpretation in KTE, reflected in the title itself: his interpretation of Kant’s concept of experience. “Kant hat einen neuen Begriff der Erfahrung entdeckt,”7 Cohen writes at the opening of the first edition of KTE (henceforth, KTE1), and while the exact nature of that new concept of experience is hard to pin down in the 1871 edition, he states it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Left-Kantianism’ and the ‘Scientific Dispute’ between Rudolf Stammler and Hermann Cohen.Elisabeth Widmer - forthcoming - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie.
    This paper argues that the ‘scientific dispute’ between Hermann Cohen and Rudolf Stammler is symptomatic of a philosophical movement of left-wing Kant interpretations at the turn of the twentieth century. By outlining influential predecessors that shaped Cohen’s and Stammler’s thinking, I show that their Kantian justifications of socialism differ regarding their conception of law, history, and the political implications that follow from their practical philosophies. Against scholars who suggest that the Marburg School’s view on socialism was a coherent school of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Elements of Völkerpsychologie in Hermann Cohen’s Mature Ethical Idealism.Elisabeth Widmer - 2021 - Idealistic Studies 51 (3):255-278.
    This paper challenges the hitherto common distinction between Hermann Cohen’s early phase of Völkerpsychologie and his later phase as a critical idealist. Recently, it has been claimed that Cohen’s turn was not a rapid conversion but a development that was already inherent to his early view. This paper argues that even in Cohen’s mature critical idealism, a thin basis of Völkerpsychologie continues to exist. Cohen’s critical programme is presented as having a twofold aim: On the one hand, it strives to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Radbruch as an Affirmative Holist. On the Question of What Ought to Be Preserved of His Philosophy.Dietmar von der Pfordten - 2008 - Ratio Juris 21 (3):387-403.
    . Gustav Radbruch is one of the most important German-speaking philosophers of law of the twentieth century. This paper raises the question of how to classify Radbruch's theories in the international context of legal philosophy and philosophy in general. Radbruch's work was mainly influenced by the southwest German school of Neo-Kantianism, represented by Windelband, Rickert, and Lask. Their theories of culture and value show an affirmative-holistic understanding of philosophy as a source of wisdom and meaningfulness. Kant, on the other hand, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Radbruch as an Affirmative Holist. On the Question of What Ought to Be Preserved of His Philosophy.Dietmar Vonderpfordten - 2008 - Ratio Juris 21 (3):387-403.
    Gustav Radbruch is one of the most important German‐speaking philosophers of law of the twentieth century. This paper raises the question of how to classify Radbruch's theories in the international context of legal philosophy and philosophy in general. Radbruch's work was mainly influenced by the southwest German school of Neo‐Kantianism, represented by Windelband, Rickert, and Lask. Their theories of culture and value show an affirmative‐holistic understanding of philosophy as a source of wisdom and meaningfulness. Kant, on the other hand, belongs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Essay Review.Volker Peckhaus - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (2):115-120.
    Jarmo Pulkkinen, The threat of logical mathematism. A study on the critique of mathematical logic in Germany at the turn of the 20th century. Frankfurt a.M:Peter Lang, 1994. Scandinavian University Studies in the Humanities and Social Sciences; 7). 186 pp. 24 DM. ISBN 3-631-47409-1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • One step forward, two steps back: Idealism in critical theory.Frieder Vogelmann - 2021 - Constellations 28 (3):322-336.
    Although Amy Allen’s critique of contemporary Frankfurt School critical theory has been widely discussed, her concern for an adequate conceptualization of reason’s intertwinement with power has not received the attention it deserves. The article shows that the diagnosis of a too idealistic account of reason forms the backbone of Allen’s charges against Habermas, Honneth and Forst, before it discusses her criteria for an adequate conceptualization of the intertwinement of reason and power. It demonstrates that Allen’s attempt to formulate such a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Scientists and the cultural politics of academic disciplines in late 19th-century Germany: Emil Du Bois-Reymond and the controversy over the role of the cultural sciences.Irmline Veit-Brause - 2001 - History of the Human Sciences 14 (4):31-56.
    This article is concerned with interactions between the natural and the human sciences. It examines a specific late 19th-century episode in their relationship and argues that the schism between the two branches of knowledge was due to cognitive factors, but consolidated through the social dynamics of institutionalized disciplines. It contends that the assignment of a social function to the human sciences to compensate for the self-destructive tendencies inherent in the technological society was expressed even by those, at the end of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From Structuralism to Culturalism: Ernst Cassirer's Philosophy of Symbolic Forms.Frédéric Vandenberghe - 2001 - European Journal of Social Theory 4 (4):479-497.
    Investigating the neo-Kantian origins of structuralism and culturalism, this article analyses the development of Cassirer's thought by following his intellectual progression from knowledge to culture, and from culture to praxis. The article is in two parts. In the first part, the author presents an analysis of Cassirer's relational conception of knowledge. In the second part, the critique of knowledge is superseded by a critique of culture. The author analyses Cassirer's anthropological philosophy of symbolic forms and critically compares it to Simmel's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • F. A. Trendelenburg and the Neglected Alternative.Andrew Specht - 2014 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (3):514-534.
    Despite his impressive influence on nineteenth-century philosophy, F. A. Trendelenburg's own philosophy has been largely ignored. However, among Kant scholars, Trendelenburg has always been remembered for his feud with Kuno Fischer over the subjectivity of space and time in Kant's philosophy. The topic of the dispute, now frequently referred to as the ?Neglected Alternative? objection, has become a prominent issue in contemporary discussions and interpretations of Kant's view of space and time. The Neglected Alternative contends that Kant unjustifiably moves from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Art, aesthetics and subjectivity.Fred Rush - 2007 - European Journal of Philosophy 15 (2):283–296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Art, Aesthetics and Subjectivity. [REVIEW]Fred Rush - 2007 - European Journal of Philosophy 15 (2):283-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reason’s genuine historicity: the establishment of a history of philosophy as a philosophical sub-discipline in Marburg Neo-Kantianism.Ursula Renz - 2021 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (4):694-717.
    . Reason’s genuine historicity: the establishment of a history of philosophy as a philosophical sub-discipline in Marburg Neo-Kantianism. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 29, Special Issue: Historical Thought in German Neo-Kantianism, Guest Editors: Katherina Kinzel and Lydia Patton, pp. 694-717.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • History of physics and the Platonic legacy: a problem in Marburg Neo-Kantianism.Paolo Pecere - 2021 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 29 (4):671-693.
    In this article, I argue that the interpretation of Kant's a priori in Marburg neo-Kantianism involved a historiographical problem concerning the Platonic interpretation of the history of exact sci...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Neo‐Kantianism in Contemporary Philosophy, edited by Rudolf A.Makkreel and SebastianLuft. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2010, viii + 331 pp. ISBN‐13: 978‐0‐253‐35389‐4 hb $70.00, ISBN‐13: 978‐0‐253‐22144‐5 pb, $27.95. [REVIEW]Stanley L. Paulson - 2012 - European Journal of Philosophy 20 (3):507-512.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The critical philosophy renewed: The bridge between Hermann Cohen's early work on Kant and later philosophy of science.Lydia Patton - 2005 - Angelaki 10 (1):109 – 118.
    German supporters of the Kantian philosophy in the late 19th century took one of two forks in the road: the fork leading to Baden, and the Southwest School of neo-Kantian philosophy, and the fork leading to Marburg, and the Marburg School, founded by Hermann Cohen. Between 1876, when Cohen came to Marburg, and 1918, the year of Cohen's death, Cohen, with his Marburg School, had a profound influence on German academia.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Toward a Theory of the Pragmatic A Priori. From Carnap to Lewis and Beyond.Thomas Mormann - 2012 - Rudolf Carnap and the Legacy of Logical Empiricism 16:113 - 132.
    The aim of this paper is make a contribution to the ongoing search for an adequate concept of the a priori element in scientific knowledge. The point of departure is C.I. Lewis’s account of a pragmatic a priori put forward in his "Mind and the World Order" (1929). Recently, Hasok Chang in "Contingent Transcendental Arguments for Metaphysical Principles" (2008) reconsidered Lewis’s pragmatic a priori and proposed to conceive it as the basic ingredient of the dynamics of an embodied scientific reason. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • ›Wirkliche Wirklichkeit‹ und ›wirklicher Lebensprozess‹ »Einbrüche des Realen« um 1848 bei Stifter und Marx.Werner Michler - 2010 - Deutsche Vierteljahrsschrift für Literaturwissenschaft Und Geistesgeschichte 84 (1):105-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Social science, epistemology, and the problem of relativism.Volker Meja & Nico Stehr - 1988 - Social Epistemology 2 (3):263 – 271.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Die Raum- und Zeitlehre Alois Riehls im Kontext realistischer Interpretationen von Kants transzendentalem Idealismus.Rudolf Meer - 2022 - Kant Studien 113 (3):459-486.
    In The Philosophical Criticism, Alois Riehl developed a realistic interpretation of Kant’s transcendental idealism based on his theory of space and time. In doing so, more than 100 years ago, he formulated an interpretation of the relation between the thing in itself and appearances that is discussed in current research as the metaphysical „dual aspect“ interpretation, although it is rarely attributed to Riehl. To reconstruct Riehl’s position, the research results of comparative studies on Moritz Schlick are systematically extended and applied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Demonstration by simulation: The philosophical significance of experiment in helmholtz's theory of perception.Patrick Joseph McDonald - 2003 - Perspectives on Science 11 (2):170-207.
    : Understanding Helmholtz's philosophy of science requires attention to his experimental practice. I sketch out such a project by showing how experiment shapes his theory of perception in three ways. One, the theory emerged out of empirical and experimental research. Two, the concept of experiment fills a critical conceptual gap in his theory of perception. Experiment functions not merely as a scientific technique, but also as a general epistemological strategy. Three, Helmholtz's experimental practice provides essential clues to the interpretation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Different Theoretical Layers of The Civilizing Process: A Response to Goudsblom and Kilminster & Wouters.Benjo Maso - 1995 - Theory, Culture and Society 12 (3):127-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Elias and the Neo-Kantians: Intellectual Backgrounds of The Civilizing Process.Benjo Maso - 1995 - Theory, Culture and Society 12 (3):43-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Naturalismus und Interpretationismus: Einige Bemerkungen zu Abels Interpretationsphilosophie.Rogério Lopes - 2018 - In Astrid Wagner & Ulrich Dirks (eds.), Abel Im Dialog: Perspektiven der Zeichen- Und Interpretationsphilosophie. De Gruyter. pp. 1219-1230.
    This article aims to investigate the extent to which Abel’s insertion in the debate on scepticism and naturalism in the Anglophone philosophical tradition, especially in the historical Strawson-Stroud debate on the success of transcendental arguments in response to the sceptical challenge, allows the creation of a conceptual scheme which refuses both the conventionalist and the naturalist position in regard to our conceptual schemas, while at the same time seeking to differentiate itself from the apriorism of the Kantian tradition. Although I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Christian Damböck:. Studien zur Philosophie im deutschsprachigen Raum 1830–1930.Hans-Ulrich Lessing - 2018 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 49 (1):149-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Christian Damböck:. Studien zur Philosophie im deutschsprachigen Raum 1830–1930: Springer, Dordrecht, 2017 (Veröffentlichungen des Instituts Wiener Kreis, Bd. 24), 237 S., 89,99 € (Hardcover), ISBN: 978-3-319-39618-7. [REVIEW]Hans-Ulrich Lessing - 2018 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 49 (1):149-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Simmel’s conception of philosophy.Turo-Kimmo Lehtonen & Olli Pyyhtinen - 2008 - Continental Philosophy Review 41 (3):301-322.
    Over the past few decades, the work of Georg Simmel (1858–1918) has again become of interest. Its reception, however, has been fairly one-sided and selective, mostly because Simmel’s philosophy has been bypassed in favor of his sociological contributions. This article examines Simmel’s explicit reflections on the nature of philosophy. Simmel defines philosophy through three aspects which, according to him, are common to all philosophical schools. First, philosophical reasoning implies the effort to think without preconditions. Second, Simmel maintains that in contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • International argument: regarding the history of the development of international philosophical communication in the nineteenth century.Vitaly Kurennoy - 2014 - Studies in East European Thought 66 (1-2):17-28.
    This article examines the internationalization of scientific and scholarly communication in the period before World War I, taking philosophy as an example. In the first part of the article, several general trends in internationalization during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries are examined. This includes the importance of international experience for Russia’s policies today towards science and education. The main part of this article is devoted to the concept of the “international argument” and provides an analysis of three types of appeal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant E a metafísica "crítica" da natureza.Diego Kosbiau Trevisan - 2015 - Doispontos 12 (2).
    O objetivo do artigo é examinar os Primeiros Princípios Metafísicos da Ciência da Natureza de Kant, obra-chave para a interpretação das filosofias da natureza do idealismo alemão, no interior d’“A Arquitetônica da Razão Pura”, a saber, como uma metafísica aplicada da substância corporal. Para tanto será inicialmente discutida a distinção, feita no prefácio à obra, entre uma parte transcendental e outra metafísico-específica da metafísica da natureza, surgindo aqui a concepção de matéria enquanto movente no espaço como conceito empírico mínimo para (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wilhelm Windelband and the problem of relativism.Katherina Kinzel - 2017 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 25 (1):84-107.
    This paper analyzes the shifts in Wilhelm Windelband’s ‘critical philosophy of values’ as it developed hand in hand with his understanding of relativism. The paper has two goals. On the one hand, by analyzing the role that relativism played in his philosophical project, it seeks to contribute to a better understanding of Windelband's intellectual development in the context of historicism and Neo-Kantianism. On the other hand, by highlighting Windelband’s contribution to the understanding of relativism, it sheds light on an important (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Ideality of Space and Time: Trendelenburg versus Kant, Fischer and Bird.Edward Kanterian - 2013 - Kantian Review 18 (2):263-288.
    Trendelenburg argued that Kant's arguments in support of transcendental idealism ignored the possibility that space and time are both ideal and real. Recently, Graham Bird has claimed that Trendelenburg (unlike his contemporary Kuno Fischer) misrepresented Kant, confusing two senses of . I defend Trendelenburg's : the ideas of space and time, as a priori and necessary, are ideal, but this does not exclude their validity in the noumenal realm. This undermines transcendental idealism. Bird's attempt to show that the Analytic considers, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mathematics, experience and laboratories: Herbart’s and Brentano’s role in the rise of scientific psychology.Wolfgang Huemer & Christoph Landerer - 2010 - History of the Human Sciences 23 (3):72-94.
    In this article we present and compare two early attempts to establish psychology as an independent scientific discipline that had considerable influence in central Europe: the theories of Johann Friedrich Herbart (1776—1841) and Franz Brentano (1838—1917). While both of them emphasize that psychology ought to be conceived as an empirical science, their conceptions show revealing differences. Herbart starts with metaphysical principles and aims at mathematizing psychology, whereas Brentano rejects all metaphysics and bases his method on a conception of inner perception (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Zwischen Universitätsreformen und katholischer Renaissance.Josef Hlade & Rudolf Meer - 2022 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 99 (2):293-328.
    With the first edition of the Philosophical Criticism, published in the 1870s and 1880s, Alois Riehl became the founder and most important representative of Realistic Criticism, and emerged as one of the leading figures in German-speaking philosophy at the turn of the century. In 1901, he applied for a chair at the Faculty of Philosophy at the University of Vienna. In the appointment procedure for the succession to Ernst Mach, he was chosen by the committee with the recommendation unico loco, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation