Switch to: References

Citations of:

Set Theory and its Logic: Revised Edition

Harvard University Press (1963)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Descriptions in Mathematical Logic.Gerard R. Renardel - 1984 - Studia Logica 43 (3):281-294.
    After a discussion of the different treatments in the literature of vacuous descriptions, the notion of descriptor is slightly generalized to function descriptor Ⅎ $\overset \rightarrow \to{y}$, so as to form partial functions φ = Ⅎ $y.A$ which satisfy $\forall \overset \rightarrow \to{x}z\leftrightarrow y=z))$. We use logic with existence predicate, as introduced by D. S. Scott, to handle partial functions, and prove that adding function descriptors to a theory based on such a logic is conservative. For theories with quantification over (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mathematics and Metaphilosophy.Justin Clarke-Doane - 2022 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    This book discusses the problem of mathematical knowledge, and its broader philosophical ramifications. It argues that the problem of explaining the (defeasible) justification of our mathematical beliefs (‘the justificatory challenge’), arises insofar as disagreement over axioms bottoms out in disagreement over intuitions. And it argues that the problem of explaining their reliability (‘the reliability challenge’), arises to the extent that we could have easily had different beliefs. The book shows that mathematical facts are not, in general, empirically accessible, contra Quine, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Structuralism and Isomorphism.C. McCarty - 2015 - Philosophia Mathematica 23 (1):1-10.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Reviews. [REVIEW][author unknown] - 2005 - History and Philosophy of Logic 26 (2):145-172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Methodological Practice and Complementary Concepts of Logical Consequence: Tarski's Model-Theoretic Consequence and Corcoran's Information-Theoretic Consequence.José M. Sagüillo - 2009 - History and Philosophy of Logic 30 (1):21-48.
    This article discusses two coextensive concepts of logical consequence that are implicit in the two fundamental logical practices of establishing validity and invalidity for premise-conclusion arguments. The premises and conclusion of an argument have information content (they ?say? something), and they have subject matter (they are ?about? something). The asymmetry between establishing validity and establishing invalidity has long been noted: validity is established through an information-processing procedure exhibiting a step-by-step deduction of the conclusion from the premise-set. Invalidity is established by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • FILOZOFIJA LOGIKE.Nijaz Ibrulj - 1999 - Sarajevo: Sarajevo Publishing.
    Aktivnost integracije i distribucije prožima cjelokupni čovjekov jezik, mišljenje i djelovanje; njegov praktični i teorijski um, uz pomoć malog broja operacija (konjunkcija, negacija, kvantifikacija) koje čine logičke konstante, sabire i razdjeljuje varijabilne elemente jezika, svijeta i mišljenja u beskonačne konačnosti (skupovi, klase, relacije, atributi) u kojima se koreliraju realne stimulacije i virtualne simulacije, čijom se konstrukcijom, rekonstrukcijom i dekonstrukcijom formiraju i transformiraju "dobro uređene formule" jezičko-gramatičkih i mentalno-psiholoških struktura koje se u svijetu saznanja imenuju pojmom svijeta, pojmom jezika, pojmom duha. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Russell's Unknown Logicism: A Study in the History and Philosophy of Mathematics.Sébastien Gandon - 2012 - Houndmills, England and New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    In this excellent book Sebastien Gandon focuses mainly on Russell's two major texts, Principa Mathematica and Principle of Mathematics, meticulously unpicking the details of these texts and bringing a new interpretation of both the mathematical and the philosophical content. Winner of The Bertrand Russell Society Book Award 2013.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Enciclopédia de Termos Lógico-Filosóficos.João Miguel Biscaia Branquinho, Desidério Murcho & Nelson Gonçalves Gomes (eds.) - 2006 - São Paulo, SP, Brasil: Martins Fontes.
    Esta enciclopédia abrange, de uma forma introdutória mas desejavelmente rigorosa, uma diversidade de conceitos, temas, problemas, argumentos e teorias localizados numa área relativamente recente de estudos, os quais tem sido habitual qualificar como «estudos lógico-filosóficos». De uma forma apropriadamente genérica, e apesar de o território teórico abrangido ser extenso e de contornos por vezes difusos, podemos dizer que na área se investiga um conjunto de questões fundamentais acerca da natureza da linguagem, da mente, da cognição e do raciocínio humanos, bem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Working from Within: The Nature and Development of Quine's Naturalism.Sander Verhaegh - 2018 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    During the past few decades, a radical shift has occurred in how philosophers conceive of the relation between science and philosophy. A great number of analytic philosophers have adopted what is commonly called a ‘naturalistic’ approach, arguing that their inquiries ought to be in some sense continuous with science. Where early analytic philosophers often relied on a sharp distinction between science and philosophy—the former an empirical discipline concerned with fact, the latter an a priori discipline concerned with meaning—philosophers today largely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Are species sets?Bradley E. Wilson - 1991 - Biology and Philosophy 6 (4):413-431.
    I construe the question Are species sets? as a question about whether species can be conceived of as sets, as the term set is understood by contemporary logicians. The question is distinct from the question Are species classes?: The conception of classes invoked by Hull and others differs from the logician's conception of a set. I argue that species can be conceived of as sets, insofar as one could identify a set with any given species and that identification would satisfy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The identity of strong indiscernibility.Horst Wessel - 1994 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 2 (5):117-134.
    The following considerations are to be seen in the framework of nontraditional theory of predication (NTP), which stems in its basic features from Sinowjew (cf. Sinowjew 1970, Sinowjew/Wessel 1975), and which is described in detail in Wessel 1989.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Theorem on Definitions of the Zermelo‐Neumann Ordinals.Hao Wang - 1967 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 13 (16-18):241-250.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is any set theory true?Joseph S. Ullian - 1969 - Philosophy of Science 36 (3):271-279.
    This paper draws its title from the recent symposium of which it was part; it attempts to respond to the question raised by that title, taking current work in set theory into account. To this end the paper contrasts set theory with number theory, examines a severe brand of set-theoretic realism that is suggested by a passage from Godel, and sketches a first-order way of looking at the results about competing extensions of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. A formalistic sentiment may be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paradoxes of intensionality.Dustin Tucker & Richmond H. Thomason - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):394-411.
    We identify a class of paradoxes that is neither set-theoretical nor semantical, but that seems to depend on intensionality. In particular, these paradoxes arise out of plausible properties of propositional attitudes and their objects. We try to explain why logicians have neglected these paradoxes, and to show that, like the Russell Paradox and the direct discourse Liar Paradox, these intensional paradoxes are recalcitrant and challenge logical analysis. Indeed, when we take these paradoxes seriously, we may need to rethink the commonly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Intensionality and paradoxes in ramsey’s ‘the foundations of mathematics’.Dustin Tucker - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):1-25.
    In , Frank Ramsey separates paradoxes into two groups, now taken to be the logical and the semantical. But he also revises the logical system developed in Whitehead and Russellthe intensional paradoxess interest in these problems seriously, then the intensional paradoxes deserve more widespread attention than they have historically received.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Sequenzen und Strukturierte Zeichenreihen.Peter Teleč - 1979 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 25 (33):531-548.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Objective probability and the mind-body relation.Paul Tappenden - 2017 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 57:8-16.
    Objective probability in quantum mechanics is often thought to involve a stochastic process whereby an actual future is selected from a range of possibilities. Everett’s seminal idea is that all possible definite futures on the pointer basis exist as components of a macroscopic linear superposition. I demonstrate that these two conceptions of what is involved in quantum processes are linked via two alternative interpretations of the mind-body relation. This leads to a fission, rather than divergence, interpretation of Everettian theory and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A Metaphysics for Semantic Internalism.Paul Tappenden - 2011 - Metaphysica 12 (2):125-136.
    The contemporary popularity of semantic externalism has arisen from so-called Twin Earth thought experiments which suggest that the representational content of a natural kind term cannot be wholly determined by processes within a speaker's body. Such arguments depend on the intuition that the extensions of natural kind terms cannot have changed as the result of the scientific investigation of natural kinds' constitutions. I demonstrate that this externalist intuition depends on an assumption about the mentality of isomorphic doppelgangers which has never (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the calculus ratiocinator.J. W. Swanson - 1965 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 8 (1-4):315 – 331.
    The project, entertained by Leibniz and others, of creating an ideal language to facilitate ratiocination, is investigated in detail. Six possible relations between the ideal language (IL) and the natural language (NL) it replaces are studied. (1) IL says exactly what NL says, but says it much more clearly. (2) IL says exactly what NL says, but does so more economically. (3) IL says exactly what NL says, but does so more succinctly. (4) IL says part of what NL says, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Translation and reduction.Lars Svenonius - 1972 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (3/4):297 - 316.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From Russell's Paradox to the Theory of Judgement: Wittgenstein and Russell on the Unity of the Proposition.Graham Stevens - 2004 - Theoria 70 (1):28-61.
    It is fairly well known that Wittgenstein's criticisms of Russell's multiple‐relation theory of judgement had a devastating effect on the latter's philosophical enterprise. The exact nature of those criticisms however, and the explanation for the severity of their consequences, has been a source of confusion and disagreement amongst both Russell and Wittgenstein scholars. In this paper, I offer an interpretation of those criticisms which shows them to be consonant with Wittgenstein's general critique of Russell's conception of logic and which serves (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Quine on naturalism, nominalism, and philosophy’s place within science.James Andrew Smith - 2021 - Synthese 198 (2):1549-1567.
    W.V. Quine is a well-known proponent of naturalism, the view on which reality is described only in science. He is also well-known for arguing that our current scientific theories commit us to the existence of abstract objects. It is tempting to believe that the naturalistic philosopher should think scientists outside of philosophy are in the best position to assess the merits of revising our current commitment to abstract objects. But Quine rejects this deferential view. On the reading of Quine’s philosophical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘Identity’ as a mereological term.Jeroen Smid - 2017 - Synthese 194 (7):2367-2385.
    The mereological predicate ‘is part of’ can be used to define the predicate ‘is identical with’. I argue that this entails that mereological theories can be ideologically simpler than nihilistic theories that do not use the notion of parthood—contrary to what has been argued by Ted Sider. Moreover, if one accepts an extensional mereology, there are good philosophical reasons apart from ideological simplicity to give a mereological definition of identity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Determinacy of abstract objects: The platonist's dilemma.Peter Simons - 1989 - Topoi 8 (1):35-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Types of plural individuals.Roger Schwarzschild - 1992 - Linguistics and Philosophy 15 (6):641 - 675.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Naïve Conception of Properties.Benjamin Schnieder - 2017 - Philosophical Issues 27 (1):322-342.
    The semantic rules that govern ordinary property discourse appear to give rise to a version of Russell's antinomy. Do we therefore have an inconsistent conception of properties? This paper firstly develops a consistent conception of properties and secondly argues that we may indeed interpret ordinary property discourse as expressing the consistent conception rather than an inconsistent one.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Ein Standardmodell Für Skalas Mengenlehre.Konrad Schultz - 1977 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 23 (27-30):405-408.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Hierarchical Propositions.Giorgio Sbardolini - 2020 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 49 (1):1-11.
    There is an apparent dilemma for hierarchical accounts of propositions, raised by Bruno Whittle : either such accounts do not offer adequate treatment of connectives and quantifiers, or they eviscerate the logic. I discuss what a plausible hierarchical conception of propositions might amount to, and show that on that conception, Whittle’s dilemma is not compelling. Thus, there are good reasons why proponents of hierarchical accounts of propositions did not see the difficulty Whittle raises.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transfinite recursion and computation in the iterative conception of set.Benjamin Rin - 2015 - Synthese 192 (8):2437-2462.
    Transfinite recursion is an essential component of set theory. In this paper, we seek intrinsically justified reasons for believing in recursion and the notions of higher computation that surround it. In doing this, we consider several kinds of recursion principles and prove results concerning their relation to one another. We then consider philosophical motivations for these formal principles coming from the idea that computational notions lie at the core of our conception of set. This is significant because, while the iterative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Set Theoretic Approach to the Simple Theory of Types.Michael D. Resnik - 1969 - Theoria 35 (3):239-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Free Logic, Description, and Virtual Classes.W. V. Quine - 1997 - Dialogue 36 (1):101-.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a logic of experience.Zane Parks - 1972 - Philosophia 2 (3):183-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Toward a logic of experience.Zane Parks - 1973 - Philosophia 3 (4):183-194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Formal Semantics: Origins, Issues, Early Impact.Barbara H. Partee - 2011 - The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6:13.
    Formal semantics and pragmatics as they have developed since the late 1960's have been shaped by fruitful interdisciplinary collaboration among linguists, philosophers, and logicians, among others, and in turn have had noticeable effects on developments in syntax, philosophy of language, computational linguistics, and cognitive science.In this paper I describe the environment in which formal semantics was born and took root, highlighting the differences in ways of thinking about natural language semantics in linguistics and in philosophy and logic. With Montague as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Classes and change.Zane Parks - 1972 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 1 (2):162 - 169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What are sets and what are they for?Alex Oliver & Timothy Smiley - 2006 - Philosophical Perspectives 20 (1):123–155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Plural descriptions and many-valued functions.Alex Oliver & Timothy Smiley - 2005 - Mind 114 (456):1039-1068.
    Russell had two theories of definite descriptions: one for singular descriptions, another for plural descriptions. We chart its development, in which ‘On Denoting’ plays a part but not the part one might expect, before explaining why it eventually fails. We go on to consider many-valued functions, since they too bring in plural terms—terms such as ‘4’ or the descriptive ‘the inhabitants of London’ which, like plain plural descriptions, stand for more than one thing. Logicians need to take plural reference seriously (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Carnap, Quine, and the humean condition.Sean Morris - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):13283-13312.
    In his “Epistemology Naturalized,” Quine embraces a form of Humeanism. In this paper, I try to work out the significance of this Humeanism. In particular, I argue that it represents an anti-metaphysical position that Quine shares with Carnap. Crucial to my account is that contrary to much contemporary thinking on metaphysics, Carnap, and Quine following him, recognize both an ontological and an epistemological sense of metaphysics. As commentators have frequently acknowledged, Carnap and Quine disagree over rejecting metaphysics in the ontological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Untersuchungen über Mengentheoretische Gleichungen.Horst Müller - 1973 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 19 (14‐18):249-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The philosophy of logical wholism.David Charles Mccarty - 1991 - Synthese 87 (1):51 - 123.
    The present paper is one installment in a lengthy task, the replacement of atomistic interpretations of Wittgenstein's Tractatus by a wholistic interpretation on which the world-in-logical-space is not constructed out of objects but objects are abstracted from out of that space. Here, general arguments against atomism are directed toward a specific target, the four aspects of the atomistic reading of Tractatus given in the Hintikkas' Investigating Wittgenstein (Hintikka & Hintikka 1986). The aspects in question are called the semantical, metaphysical, epistemological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Representation, intentionality, and quantifiers.Timothy Mccarthy - 1984 - Synthese 60 (3):369 - 411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Substitutional Characterization of First-Order Logical Truth.Matthew McKeon - 2004 - History and Philosophy of Logic 25 (3):205-224.
    I consider the well-known criticism of Quine's characterization of first-order logical truth that it expands the class of logical truths beyond what is sanctioned by the model-theoretic account. Briefly, I argue that at best the criticism is shallow and can be answered with slight alterations in Quine's account. At worse the criticism is defective because, in part, it is based on a misrepresentation of Quine. This serves not only to clarify Quine's position, but also to crystallize what is and what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Four simple systems of modal propositional logic.Gerald J. Massey - 1965 - Philosophy of Science 32 (3/4):342-355.
    Four progressively ambitious systems of modal propositional logic are set forth, together with decision procedures. The simultaneous employment of parenthesis notation and parenthesis-free notation, the dual use of symbols as primitive and defined, and the introduction of a new modal operator (the truth operator) are the principal devices used to effect the development of these logics. The first two logics turn out to be "the same" as two of von Wright's systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • L'identité est-elle relative?Maryvonne Longeart-Roth - 1981 - Dialogue 20 (4):697-713.
    La relation d'identité est-elle univoque, ou est-elle au contraire relative au concept sous lequel le jugement est énoncé? Depuis quelques années, parmi les philosophes anglo-américains, partisans et adversaires de la thèse que l'on a appelée « la relativité de l'identité », se sont affrontés sur ce point.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A renaissance of empiricism in the recent philosophy of mathematics.Imre Lakatos - 1976 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (3):201-223.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Russell's 1903 - 1905 Anticipation of the Lambda Calculus.Kevin Klement - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (1):15-37.
    It is well known that the circumflex notation used by Russell and Whitehead to form complex function names in Principia Mathematica played a role in inspiring Alonzo Church's “lambda calculus” for functional logic developed in the 1920s and 1930s. Interestingly, earlier unpublished manuscripts written by Russell between 1903–1905—surely unknown to Church—contain a more extensive anticipation of the essential details of the lambda calculus. Russell also anticipated Schönfinkel's combinatory logic approach of treating multiargument functions as functions having other functions as value. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The empty set, the Singleton, and the ordered pair.Akihiro Kanamori - 2003 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (3):273-298.
    For the modern set theorist the empty set Ø, the singleton {a}, and the ordered pair 〈x, y〉 are at the beginning of the systematic, axiomatic development of set theory, both as a field of mathematics and as a unifying framework for ongoing mathematics. These notions are the simplest building locks in the abstract, generative conception of sets advanced by the initial axiomatization of Ernst Zermelo [1908a] and are quickly assimilated long before the complexities of Power Set, Replacement, and Choice (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Types in logic and mathematics before 1940.Fairouz Kamareddine, Twan Laan & Rob Nederpelt - 2002 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (2):185-245.
    In this article, we study the prehistory of type theory up to 1910 and its development between Russell and Whitehead's Principia Mathematica ([71], 1910-1912) and Church's simply typed λ-calculus of 1940. We first argue that the concept of types has always been present in mathematics, though nobody was incorporating them explicitly as such, before the end of the 19th century. Then we proceed by describing how the logical paradoxes entered the formal systems of Frege, Cantor and Peano concentrating on Frege's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An axiom schema of comprehension of zermelo–fraenkel–skolem set theory.Johannes Heidema - 1990 - History and Philosophy of Logic 11 (1):59-65.
    Unrestricted use of the axiom schema of comprehension, ?to every mathematically (or set-theoretically) describable property there corresponds the set of all mathematical (or set-theoretical) objects having that property?, leads to contradiction. In set theories of the Zermelo?Fraenkel?Skolem (ZFS) style suitable instances of the comprehension schema are chosen ad hoc as axioms, e.g.axioms which guarantee the existence of unions, intersections, pairs, subsets, empty set, power sets and replacement sets. It is demonstrated that a uniform syntactic description may be given of acceptable (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On bracketing names and quantifiers in first-order logic.Jacek Pasniczek - 1999 - History and Philosophy of Logic 20 (3-4):239-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark