Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The EBM Argument Hygiene Campaign.Peter Cramer - 2013 - Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 19 (3):447-453.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Investigation of Biases and Compensatory Strategies Using a Probabilistic Variant of the Wisconsin Card Sorting Test.Alexis B. Craig, Matthew E. Phillips, Andrew Zaldivar, Rajan Bhattacharyya & Jeffrey L. Krichmar - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The dark side of dialog.Justin J. Couchman, Gwenievere A. Birster & Mariana V. C. Coutinho - 2018 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are humans good intuitive statisticians after all? Rethinking some conclusions from the literature on judgment under uncertainty.L. Cosmides - 1996 - Cognition 58 (1):1-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • Relevant features and statistical models of generalization.James E. Corter - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):653-654.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Practicality of Virtue Ethics.Daniel Coren - 2021 - Journal of Value Inquiry 57 (2):295-318.
    Using research in social psychology, philosophers such as Gilbert Harman and John Doris argue that human beings do not have – and cannot acquire – character traits such as virtues. Along with defenders of virtue ethics such as Julia Annas and Rachana Kamtekar, they assume that this constitutes a dangerous attack on virtue ethics. I argue that even if virtues and vices did not exist and everyone accepted that truth, (1) we would continue to make attributions of character traits in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Stuart Mill’s Political Pessimism.Paul Corcoran - 2019 - The European Legacy 24 (5):471-491.
    ABSTRACTJohn Stuart Mill devoted much of his life to developing a ‘science of morality’ to enhance the social, moral and intellectual character of individuals and society as a whole. His liberal as...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A cognitive account of belief: a tentative road map.Michael H. Connors & Peter W. Halligan - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Action as a fast and frugal heuristic.Terry Connolly - 1999 - Minds and Machines 9 (4):479-496.
    Decision making is usually viewed as involving a period of thought, while the decision maker assesses options, their likely consequences, and his or her preferences, and selects the preferred option. The process ends in a terminating action. In this view errors of thought will inevitably show up as errors of action; costs of thinking are to be balanced against costs of decision errors. Fast and frugal heuristics research has shown that, in some environments, modest thought can lead to excellent action. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Idealisations in normative models.Mark Colyvan - 2013 - Synthese 190 (8):1337-1350.
    In this paper I discuss the kinds of idealisations invoked in normative theories—logic, epistemology, and decision theory. I argue that very often the so-called norms of rationality are in fact mere idealisations invoked to make life easier. As such, these idealisations are not too different from various idealisations employed in scientific modelling. Examples of the latter include: fluids are incompressible (in fluid mechanics), growth rates are constant (in population ecology), and the gravitational influence of distant bodies can be ignored (in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Cooperation, psychological game theory, and limitations of rationality in social interaction.Andrew M. Colman - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (2):139-153.
    Rational choice theory enjoys unprecedented popularity and influence in the behavioral and social sciences, but it generates intractable problems when applied to socially interactive decisions. In individual decisions, instrumental rationality is defined in terms of expected utility maximization. This becomes problematic in interactive decisions, when individuals have only partial control over the outcomes, because expected utility maximization is undefined in the absence of assumptions about how the other participants will behave. Game theory therefore incorporates not only rationality but also common (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The controversy about irrationality.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):510.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Status of the rationality assumption in psychology.Marvin S. Cohen - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):332-333.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • On the psychology of prediction: Whose is the fallacy?L. Jonathan Cohen - 1979 - Cognition 7 (December):385-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • Do, or should, all human decisions conform to the norms of a consumer-oriented culture?L. Jonathan Cohen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1):12-13.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can irrationality be discussed accurately?L. Jonathan Cohen - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):736.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can human irrationality be experimentally demonstrated?L. Jonathan Cohen - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):317-370.
    The object of this paper is to show why recent research in the psychology of deductive and probabilistic reasoning does not have.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   477 citations  
  • Belief, acceptance, and probability.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (2):248-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are there any a priori constraints on the study of rationality?L. Jonathan Cohen - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):359-370.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Attitudes toward risk are complicated: experimental evidence for the re-individuation approach to risk-attitudes.Haim Cohen, Anat Maril, Sun Bleicher & Ittay Nissan-Rozen - 2022 - Philosophical Studies 179 (8):2553-2577.
    We present experimental evidence that supports the thesis :602–625, 2015, Br J Philos Sci 70:77–102, 2019; Bradley in Decisions theory with a human face, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2017; Goldschmidt and Nissan-Rozen in Synthese 198:7553–7575, 2021) that people might positively or negatively desire risky prospects conditional on only some of the prospects’ outcomes obtaining. We argue that this evidence has important normative implications for the central debate in normative decision theory between two general approaches on how to rationalize several common (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Are people programmed to commit fallacies? Further thoughts about the interpretation of experimental data on probability judgment.L. Jonathan Cohen - 1982 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 12 (3):251–274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Intuitions are Used as Evidence in Philosophy.Nevin Climenhaga - 2018 - Mind 127 (505):69-104.
    In recent years a growing number of philosophers writing about the methodology of philosophy have defended the surprising claim that philosophers do not use intuitions as evidence. In this paper I defend the contrary view that philosophers do use intuitions as evidence. I argue that this thesis is the best explanation of several salient facts about philosophical practice. First, philosophers tend to believe propositions which they find intuitive. Second, philosophers offer error theories for intuitions that conflict with their theories. Finally, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Undecidability and opacity of metacognition in animals and humans.Kevin B. Clark & Derrick L. Hassert - 2013 - Frontiers in Psychology 4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Unpredictable homeodynamic and ambient constraints on irrational decision making of aneural and neural foragers.Kevin B. Clark - 2019 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Reasons, robots and the extended mind.Andy Clark - 2001 - Mind and Language 16 (2):121-145.
    A suitable project for the new Millenium is to radically reconfigure our image of human rationality. Such a project is already underway, within the Cognitive Sciences, under the umbrellas of work in Situated Cognition, Distributed and De-centralized Cogition, Real-world Robotics and Artificial Life1. Such approaches, however, are often criticized for giving certain aspects of rationality too wide a berth. They focus their attention on on such superficially poor cousins as.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Gerd Gigerenzer, Gut feelings: Short cuts to better decision making. [REVIEW]Christine Clavien - 2010 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13 (1):113-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemic norms and evolutionary success.Murray Clarke - 1990 - Synthese 85 (2):231 - 244.
    Recent debates concerning the nature of epistemic justification primarily turn on two distinctions: the objective-subjective distinction and the internal-external distinction. John Pollock has defended a view that is both internalist and subjectivist. He has provided a novel, naturalized account of epistemic justification. In this paper, I argue that data from cognitive psychology and biology is radically at odds with Pollock's project.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Assertion, Belief, and Context.Roger Clarke - 2018 - Synthese 195 (11):4951-4977.
    This paper argues for a treatment of belief as essentially sensitive to certain features of context. The first part gives an argument that we must take belief to be context-sensitive in the same way that assertion is, if we are to preserve appealing principles tying belief to sincere assertion. In particular, whether an agent counts as believing that p in a context depends on the space of alternative possibilities the agent is considering in that context. One and the same doxastic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Moral Foreign-Language Effect.Heather Cipolletti, Steven McFarlane & Christine Weissglass - 2016 - Philosophical Psychology 29 (1):23-40.
    Many have argued that moral judgment is driven by one of two types of processes. Rationalists argue that reasoned processes are the source of moral judgments, whereas sentimentalists argue that emotional processes are. We provide evidence that both positions are mistaken; there are multiple mental processes involved in moral judgment, and it is possible to manipulate which process is engaged when considering moral dilemmas by presenting them in a non-native language. The Foreign-Language Effect is the activation of systematic reasoning processes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Did Freud rely on the tally argument to meet the argument from suggestibility?F. Cioffi - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):230-231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bounded awareness: what you fail to see can hurt you.D. Chugh, M. H. Bazerman & D. DeMoss - 2007 - Mind and Society 6 (1):1-18.
    ObjectiveWe argue that people often fail to perceive and process stimuli easily available to them. In other words, we challenge the tacit assumption that awareness is unbounded and provide evidence that humans regularly fail to see and use stimuli and information easily available to them. We call this phenomenon “bounded awareness” (Bazerman and Chugh in Frontiers of social psychology: negotiations, Psychology Press: College Park 2005). Findings We begin by first describing perceptual mental processes in which obvious information is missed—that is, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Cognitive Biases and Errors as Cause—and Journalistic Best Practices as Effect.Sue Ellen Christian - 2013 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 28 (3):160-174.
    This article argues that basic ethical principles of U.S. journalism as described in the Society of Professional Journalists' Code of Ethics are the result of, and a response to, cognitive bias and error. Cognitive biases and errors necessitate journalistic best practices to correct or attenuate them. Social cognitive processes explored include stereotyping, confirmation bias, and attribution. These concepts are noteworthy because each may be activated by the practice of journalism, and each has been shown to be susceptible to attenuation through (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Brains, genes, and language evolution: A new synthesis.Morten H. Christiansen & Nick Chater - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (5):537-558.
    Our target article argued that a genetically specified Universal Grammar (UG), capturing arbitrary properties of languages, is not tenable on evolutionary grounds, and that the close fit between language and language learners arises because language is shaped by the brain, rather than the reverse. Few commentaries defend a genetically specified UG. Some commentators argue that we underestimate the importance of processes of cultural transmission; some propose additional cognitive and brain mechanisms that may constrain language and perhaps differentiate humans from nonhuman (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Many Meanings of ‘Heuristic’.Sheldon J. Chow - 2015 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 66 (4):977-1016.
    A survey of contemporary philosophical and scientific literatures reveals that different authors employ the term ‘heuristic’ in ways that deviate from, and are sometimes inconsistent with, one another. Given its widespread use in philosophy and cognitive science generally, it is striking that there appears to be little concern for a clear account of what phenomena heuristics pick out or refer to. In response, I consider several accounts of ‘heuristic’, and I draw a number of distinctions between different sorts of heuristics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • What’s wrong with the evolutionary argument against naturalism?Geoff Childers - 2011 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 69 (3):193-204.
    Alvin Plantinga has argued that evolutionary naturalism (the idea that God does not tinker with evolution) undermines its own rationality. Natural selection is concerned with survival and reproduction, and false beliefs conjoined with complementary motivational drives could serve the same aims as true beliefs. Thus, argues Plantinga, if we believe we evolved naturally, we should not think our beliefs are, on average, likely to be true, including our beliefs in evolution and naturalism. I argue herein that our cognitive faculties are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Developmental changes in probabilistic reasoning: The role of cognitive capacity, instructions, thinking styles and relevant knowledge.Francesca Chiesi, Caterina Primi & Kinga Morsanyi - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The epistemological status of lay intuition.Christopher Cherniak - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The rational analysis of mind and behavior.Nick Chater & Mike Oaksford - 2000 - Synthese 122 (1-2):93-131.
    Rational analysis (Anderson 1990, 1991a) is an empiricalprogram of attempting to explain why the cognitive system isadaptive, with respect to its goals and the structure of itsenvironment. We argue that rational analysis has two importantimplications for philosophical debate concerning rationality. First,rational analysis provides a model for the relationship betweenformal principles of rationality (such as probability or decisiontheory) and everyday rationality, in the sense of successfulthought and action in daily life. Second, applying the program ofrational analysis to research on human reasoning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Prospect relativity: how choice options influence decision under risk.Neil Stewart, Nick Chater, Henry P. Stott & Stian Reimers - 2003 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 132 (1):23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Probabilistic models of cognition: Conceptual foundations.Nick Chater & Alan Yuille - 2006 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10 (7):287-291.
    Remarkable progress in the mathematics and computer science of probability has led to a revolution in the scope of probabilistic models. In particular, ‘sophisticated’ probabilistic methods apply to structured relational systems such as graphs and grammars, of immediate relevance to the cognitive sciences. This Special Issue outlines progress in this rapidly developing field, which provides a potentially unifying perspective across a wide range of domains and levels of explanation. Here, we introduce the historical and conceptual foundations of the approach, explore (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Many reasons or just one: How response mode affects reasoning in the conjunction problem.Ralph Hertwig Valerie M. Chase - 1998 - Thinking and Reasoning 4 (4):319 – 352.
    Forty years of experimentation on class inclusion and its probabilistic relatives have led to inconsistent results and conclusions about human reasoning. Recent research on the conjunction "fallacy" recapitulates this history. In contrast to previous results, we found that a majority of participants adhere to class inclusion in the classic Linda problem. We outline a theoretical framework that attributes the contradictory results to differences in statistical sophistication and to differences in response mode-whether participants are asked for probability estimates or ranks-and propose (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Critical tests of the continuous dual-process model of recognition.Jihyun Cha & Ian G. Dobbins - 2021 - Cognition 215 (C):104827.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Although optimal models are useful, optimality claims are not that common.Claire Chambers & Konrad Paul Kording - 2018 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The scaffolding of psychoanalysis.Peter Caws - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (2):229-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cognitive biases can affect moral intuitions about cognitive enhancement.Lucius Caviola, Adriano Mannino, Julian Savulescu & Nadira Faber - 2014 - Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience 8.
    Research into cognitive biases that impair human judgment has mostly been applied to the area of economic decision-making. Ethical decision-making has been comparatively neglected. Since ethical decisions often involve very high individual as well as collective stakes, analyzing how cognitive biases affect them can be expected to yield important results. In this theoretical article, we consider the ethical debate about cognitive enhancement and suggest a number of cognitive biases that are likely to affect moral intuitions and judgments about CE: status (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Research, Digital Health Information and Promises of Privacy: Revisiting the Issue of Consent.Timothy Caulfield, Blake Murdoch & Ubaka Ogbogu - 2020 - Canadian Journal of Bioethics / Revue canadienne de bioéthique 3 (1):164-171.
    The obligation to maintain the privacy of patients and research participants is foundational to biomedical research. But there is growing concern about the challenges of keeping participant information private and confidential. A number of recent studies have highlighted how emerging computational strategies can be used to identify or reidentify individuals in health data repositories managed by public or private institutions. Some commentators have suggested the entire concept of privacy and anonymity is “dead”, and this raises legal and ethical questions about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reasoning logically in cognitive domains.Claudia Casadio - 2016 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 24 (4):628-638.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An experimental and simulation study of the impact of emotional information on analogical reasoning.Ariana A. Castro, John E. Hummel & Howard Berenbaum - 2023 - Cognition 238 (C):105510.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Which Firms Get Punished for Unethical Behavior? Explaining Variation in Stock Market Reactions to Corporate Misconduct.Edward J. Carberry, Peter-Jan Engelen & Marc Van Essen - 2018 - Business Ethics Quarterly 28 (2):119-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The illusion of conscious will.Peter Carruthers - 2007 - Synthese 159 (2):197 - 213.
    Wegner (Wegner, D. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. MIT Press) argues that conscious will is an illusion, citing a wide range of empirical evidence. I shall begin by surveying some of his arguments. Many are unsuccessful. But one—an argument from the ubiquity of self-interpretation—is more promising. Yet is suffers from an obvious lacuna, offered by so-called ‘dual process’ theories of reasoning and decision making (Evans, J., & Over, D. (1996). Rationality and reasoning. Psychology Press; Stanovich, K. (1999). Who is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations