Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Begriffsschrift: Eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens.Gottlob Frege - 1879 - Halle a.d.S.: Louis Nebert.
    Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens / von Dr. Gottlob Frege,...Date de l'edition originale : 1879Ce livre est la reproduction fidele d'une oeuvre publiee avant 1920 et fait partie d'une collection de livres reimprimes a la demande editee par Hachette Livre, dans le cadre d'un partenariat avec la Bibliotheque nationale de France, offrant l'opportunite d'acceder a des ouvrages anciens et souvent rares issus des fonds patrimoniaux de la BnF.Les oeuvres faisant partie de cette collection ont ete numerisees (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   318 citations  
  • La logique de Leibniz d'après des documents inedits. [REVIEW]George Martin Duncan - 1903 - Philosophical Review 12 (6):649-664.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • The Absence of Multiple Universes of Discourse in the 1936 Tarski Consequence-Definition Paper.John Corcoran & José Miguel Sagüillo - 2011 - History and Philosophy of Logic 32 (4):359-374.
    This paper discusses the history of the confusion and controversies over whether the definition of consequence presented in the 11-page 1936 Tarski consequence-definition paper is based on a monistic fixed-universe framework?like Begriffsschrift and Principia Mathematica. Monistic fixed-universe frameworks, common in pre-WWII logic, keep the range of the individual variables fixed as the class of all individuals. The contrary alternative is that the definition is predicated on a pluralistic multiple-universe framework?like the 1931 Gödel incompleteness paper. A pluralistic multiple-universe framework recognizes multiple (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The power of the hexagon.Jean-Yves Béziau - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (1-2):1-43.
    The hexagon of opposition is an improvement of the square of opposition due to Robert Blanché. After a short presentation of the square and its various interpretations, we discuss two important problems related with the square: the problem of the I-corner and the problem of the O-corner. The meaning of the notion described by the I-corner does not correspond to the name used for it. In the case of the O-corner, the problem is not a wrong-name problem but a no-name (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Logic may be simple. Logic, congruence and algebra.Jean-Yves Béziau - 1997 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 5:129-147.
    This paper is an attempt to clear some philosophical questions about the nature of logic by setting up a mathematical framework. The notion of congruence in logic is defined. A logical structure in which there is no non-trivial congruence relation, like some paraconsistent logics, is called simple. The relations between simplicity, the replacement theorem and algebraization of logic are studied (including MacLane-Curry’s theorem and a discussion about Curry’s algebras). We also examine how these concepts are related to such notions as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • An Investigation of the Laws of Thought, on Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities.Alonzo Church - 1951 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 16 (3):224-225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • An Investigation of the Laws of Thought: On Which Are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities.George Boole - 2009 - [New York]: Cambridge University Press.
    Self-taught mathematician and father of Boolean algebra, George Boole (1815-1864) published An Investigation of the Laws of Thought in 1854. In this highly original investigation of the fundamental laws of human reasoning, a sequel to ideas he had explored in earlier writings, Boole uses the symbolic language of mathematics to establish a method to examine the nature of the human mind using logic and the theory of probabilities. Boole considers language not just as a mode of expression, but as a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   120 citations  
  • Sur la structuration du tableau Des connectifs interpropositionnels binaires.Robert Blanché - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (1):17-18.
    La théorie de la quaternalité, telle que Piaget et Gottschalk l'ont appliquée aux connectifs binaires du calcul bivalent, appelle quelques précisions et compléments.Les seize connectifs ne comportent que deux quaternes complets: celui des jonctions et celui des implications. Leurs similitudes formelles ne doivent pas dissimuler une différence dans leur mode de construction. Elle apparaît sur leurs diagrammes (inspirés du “carré logique” traditionnel) par la place de la cellule initiale et par celles des signes barrés du trait vertical de la négation:En (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Logic and Religion.Jean-Yves Beziau & Ricardo Silvestre - 2017 - Logica Universalis 11 (1):1-12.
    This paper introduces the special issue on Logic and Religion of the journal Logica Universalis (Springer). The issue contains the following articles: Logic and Religion, by Jean-Yves Beziau and Ricardo Silvestre; Thinking Negation in Early Hinduism and Classical Indian Philosophy, by Purushottama Bilimoria; Karma Theory, Determinism, Fatalism and Freedom of Will, by Ricardo Sousa Silvestre; From Logic in Islam to Islamic Logic, by Musa Akrami; Leibniz’s Ontological Proof of the Existence of God and the Problem of Impossible Objects, by Wolfgang (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Disentangling Contradiction from Contrariety via Incompatibility.Jean-Yves Beziau - 2016 - Logica Universalis 10 (2-3):157-170.
    Contradiction is often confused with contrariety. We propose to disentangle contrariety from contradiction using the hexagon of opposition, providing a clear and distinct characterization of three notions: contrariety, contradiction, incompatibility. At the same time, this hexagonal structure describes and explains the relations between them.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The mathematical origins of nineteenth-century algebra of logic.Volker Peckhaus - 2011 - In Leila Haaparanta (ed.), The development of modern logic. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 159.
    This chapter discusses the complex conditions for the emergence of 19th-century symbolic logic. The main scope will be on the mathematical motives leading to the interest in logic; the philosophical context will be dealt with only in passing. The main object of study will be the algebra of logic in its British and German versions. Special emphasis will be laid on the systems of George Boole and above all of his German follower Ernst Schröder.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • george boole.John Corcoran - 2006 - In Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. macmillan.
    2006. George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA. -/- George Boole (1815-1864), whose name lives among modern computer-related sciences in Boolean Algebra, Boolean Logic, Boolean Operations, and the like, is one of the most celebrated logicians of all time. Ironically, his actual writings often go unread and his actual contributions to logic are virtually unknown—despite the fact that he was one of the clearest writers in the field. Working with various students including Susan Wood and Sriram (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Adolf Lindenbaum: Notes on his Life, with Bibliography and Selected References.Jan Zygmunt & Robert Purdy - 2014 - Logica Universalis 8 (3-4):285-320.
    Notes on the life of Adolf Lindenbaum, a complete bibliography of his published works, and selected references to his unpublished results.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Logical Squares for Classical Logic Sentences.Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 2016 - Logica Universalis 10 (2-3):293-312.
    In this paper, with reference to relationships of the traditional square of opposition, we establish all the relations of the square of opposition between complex sentences built from the 16 binary and four unary propositional connectives of the classical propositional calculus. We illustrate them by means of many squares of opposition and, corresponding to them—octagons, hexagons or other geometrical objects.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Historical Development of Modern Logic.Jean van Heijenoort - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (3-4):327-337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics.Atwell Turquette - 1958 - Philosophical Review 67 (1):113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • Drei Briefe an Otto Neurath.Alfred Tarski - 1992 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 43:1-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The theory of Representations for Boolean Algebras.M. H. Stone - 1936 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 1 (3):118-119.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Investigations into the sentential calculus with identity.Roman Suszko & Stephen L. Bloom - 1972 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 13 (3):289-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Frege's Judgement Stroke and the Conception of Logic as the Study of Inference not Consequence.Nicholas J. J. Smith - 2009 - Philosophy Compass 4 (4):639-665.
    One of the most striking differences between Frege's Begriffsschrift (logical system) and standard contemporary systems of logic is the inclusion in the former of the judgement stroke: a symbol which marks those propositions which are being asserted , that is, which are being used to express judgements . There has been considerable controversy regarding both the exact purpose of the judgement stroke, and whether a system of logic should include such a symbol. This paper explains the intended role of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Dual Intuitionistic Logic and a Variety of Negations: The Logic of Scientific Research.Yaroslav Shramko - 2005 - Studia Logica 80 (2-3):347-367.
    We consider a logic which is semantically dual (in some precise sense of the term) to intuitionistic. This logic can be labeled as “falsification logic”: it embodies the Popperian methodology of scientific discovery. Whereas intuitionistic logic deals with constructive truth and non-constructive falsity, and Nelson's logic takes both truth and falsity as constructive notions, in the falsification logic truth is essentially non-constructive as opposed to falsity that is conceived constructively. We also briefly clarify the relationships of our falsification logic to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • From Analogical Proportion to Logical Proportions.Henri Prade & Gilles Richard - 2013 - Logica Universalis 7 (4):441-505.
    Given a 4-tuple of Boolean variables (a, b, c, d), logical proportions are modeled by a pair of equivalences relating similarity indicators ( \({a \wedge b}\) and \({\overline{a} \wedge \overline{b}}\) ), or dissimilarity indicators ( \({a \wedge \overline{b}}\) and \({\overline{a} \wedge b}\) ) pertaining to the pair (a, b), to the ones associated with the pair (c, d). There are 120 semantically distinct logical proportions. One of them models the analogical proportion which corresponds to a statement of the form “a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Model Theory.Michael Makkai, C. C. Chang & H. J. Keisler - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (3):1096.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   403 citations  
  • The Pursuit of an Implication for the Logics L3A and L3B.Alejandro Hernández-Tello, José Arrazola Ramírez & Mauricio Osorio Galindo - 2017 - Logica Universalis 11 (4):507-524.
    The authors of Beziau and Franceschetto work with logics that have the property of not satisfying any of the formulations of the principle of non contradiction, Béziau and Franceschetto also analyze, among the three-valued logics, which of these logics satisfy this property. They prove that there exist only four of such logics, but only two of them are worthwhile to study. The language of these logics does not consider implication as a connective. However, the enrichment of a language with an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Jean van Heijenoort: Kaleidoscope. [REVIEW]Anita Burdman Feferman - 2012 - Logica Universalis 6 (3-4):277-291.
    Leitmotifs in the life of Jean van Heijenoort.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Early history of the association for symbolic logic.C. J. Ducasse & Haskell B. Curry - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (3):255-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Search for Mathematical Roots, 1870-1940: Logics, Set Theories and the Foundations of Mathematics from Cantor through Russell to Gödel.I. Grattan-Guinness - 2011 - Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press.
    While many books have been written about Bertrand Russell's philosophy and some on his logic, I. Grattan-Guinness has written the first comprehensive history of the mathematical background, content, and impact of the mathematical logic and philosophy of mathematics that Russell developed with A. N. Whitehead in their Principia mathematica (1910-1913).? This definitive history of a critical period in mathematics includes detailed accounts of the two principal influences upon Russell around 1900: the set theory of Cantor and the mathematical logic of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Birth of Model Theory: Lowenheim's Theorem in the Frame of the Theory of Relatives.Calixto Badesa - 2004 - Princeton University Press.
    Löwenheim's theorem reflects a critical point in the history of mathematical logic, for it marks the birth of model theory--that is, the part of logic that concerns the relationship between formal theories and their models. However, while the original proofs of other, comparably significant theorems are well understood, this is not the case with Löwenheim's theorem. For example, the very result that scholars attribute to Löwenheim today is not the one that Skolem--a logician raised in the algebraic tradition, like Löwenheim--appears (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik.D. Hilbert & W. Ackermann - 1928 - Annalen der Philosophie Und Philosophischen Kritik 7:157-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   204 citations  
  • Symbolic Logic.John Venn - 1881 - Mind 6 (24):574-581.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Logic is not Logic.Jean-Ives Béziau - 2010 - Abstracta 6 (1):73-102.
    In this paper we discuss the difference between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Making Sense of Paraconsistent Logic: The Nature of Logic, Classical Logic and Paraconsistent Logic.Koji Tanaka - 2013 - In Francesco Berto, Edwin Mares, Koji Tanaka & Francesco Paoli (eds.), Paraconsistency: Logic and Applications. Springer. pp. 15--25.
    Max Cresswell and Hilary Putnam seem to hold the view, often shared by classical logicians, that paraconsistent logic has not been made sense of, despite its well-developed mathematics. In this paper, I examine the nature of logic in order to understand what it means to make sense of logic. I then show that, just as one can make sense of non-normal modal logics (as Cresswell demonstrates), we can make `sense' of paraconsistent logic. Finally, I turn the tables on classical logicians (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • O Zasadzie sprzecznósci u. Arystotelesa. Ueber den Satz des Widerspruchs bei Aristoteles.Jan Lukasiewicz - 1910 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 18 (6):14-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Identity, logic and structure.J. Y. Béziau - 1996 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 25:89-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • 30 treatise on universal algebra (gif images).Alfred North Whitehead - unknown
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations