Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Mathematical Thought and its Objects.Charles Parsons - 2007 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Charles Parsons examines the notion of object, with the aim to navigate between nominalism, denying that distinctively mathematical objects exist, and forms of Platonism that postulate a transcendent realm of such objects. He introduces the central mathematical notion of structure and defends a version of the structuralist view of mathematical objects, according to which their existence is relative to a structure and they have no more of a 'nature' than that confers on them. Parsons also analyzes the concept of intuition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Kant on geometry and spatial intuition.Michael Friedman - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):231-255.
    I use recent work on Kant and diagrammatic reasoning to develop a reconsideration of central aspects of Kant’s philosophy of geometry and its relation to spatial intuition. In particular, I reconsider in this light the relations between geometrical concepts and their schemata, and the relationship between pure and empirical intuition. I argue that diagrammatic interpretations of Kant’s theory of geometrical intuition can, at best, capture only part of what Kant’s conception involves and that, for example, they cannot explain why Kant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Classical sources for the concepts of analysis and synthesis.Marco Panza - 1997 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science:365-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Euclidean Diagram.Kenneth Manders - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 80--133.
    This chapter gives a detailed study of diagram-based reasoning in Euclidean plane geometry (Books I, III), as well as an exploration how to characterise a geometric practice. First, an account is given of diagram attribution: basic geometrical claims are classified as exact (equalities, proportionalities) or co-exact (containments, contiguities); exact claims may only be inferred from prior entries in the demonstration text, but co-exact claims may be asserted based on what is seen in the diagram. Diagram control by constructions is necessary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • A formal system for euclid’s elements.Jeremy Avigad, Edward Dean & John Mumma - 2009 - Review of Symbolic Logic 2 (4):700--768.
    We present a formal system, E, which provides a faithful model of the proofs in Euclid's Elements, including the use of diagrammatic reasoning.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  • Philosophy of mathematics and deductive structure in Euclid's Elements.Ian Mueller - 1981 - Mineola, N.Y.: Dover Publications.
    A survey of Euclid's Elements, this text provides an understanding of the classical Greek conception of mathematics and its similarities to modern views as well as its differences. It focuses on philosophical, foundational, and logical questions — rather than strictly historical and mathematical issues — and features several helpful appendixes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics: A Study in Cognitive History.Reviel Netz - 1999 - Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press.
    An examination of the emergence of the phenomenon of deductive argument in classical Greek mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  • The Definitions of Fundamental Geometric Entities Contained in Book I of Euclids Elements.Lucio Russo - 1998 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 52 (3):195-219.
    OElig;he thesis is sustained that the definitions of fundamental geometric entities which open Euclids Elements actually are excerpts from the Definitions by Heron of Alexandria, interpolated in late antiquity into Euclids treatise. As a consequence, one of the main bases of the traditional Platonist interpretation of Euclid is refuted. Arguments about the constructivist nature of Euclids mathematical philosophy are given.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics a Study in Cognitive History.Jenz Høyrup - 1999
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Analysis and Synthesis in Mathematics,.Michael Otte & Marco Panza (eds.) - 1997 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Philosophical Relevance of Category Theory.Colin McLarty - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What structuralism achieves.C. McLarty - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 354--369.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Proofs, pictures, and Euclid.John Mumma - 2010 - Synthese 175 (2):255 - 287.
    Though pictures are often used to present mathematical arguments, they are not typically thought to be an acceptable means for presenting mathematical arguments rigorously. With respect to the proofs in the Elements in particular, the received view is that Euclid's reliance on geometric diagrams undermines his efforts to develop a gap-free deductive theory. The central difficulty concerns the generality of the theory. How can inferences made from a particular diagrams license general mathematical results? After surveying the history behind the received (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Euclid and His Twentieth Century Rivals: Diagrams in the Logic of Euclidean Geometry.Nathaniel Miller - 2007 - Center for the Study of Language and Inf.
    Twentieth-century developments in logic and mathematics have led many people to view Euclid’s proofs as inherently informal, especially due to the use of diagrams in proofs. In _Euclid and His Twentieth-Century Rivals_, Nathaniel Miller discusses the history of diagrams in Euclidean Geometry, develops a formal system for working with them, and concludes that they can indeed be used rigorously. Miller also introduces a diagrammatic computer proof system, based on this formal system. This volume will be of interest to mathematicians, computer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Diagram-Based Geometric Practice.Kenneth Manders - 2008 - In Paolo Mancosu (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. pp. 65--79.
    This chapter provides a survey of issues about diagrams in traditional geometrical reasoning. After briefly refuting several common philosophical objections, and giving a sketch of diagram-based reasoning practice in Euclidean plane geometry, discussion focuses first on problems of diagram sensitivity, and then on the relationship between uniform treatment and geometrical generality. Here, one finds a balance between representationally enforced unresponsiveness (to differences among diagrams) and the intellectual agent's contribution to such unresponsiveness that is somewhat different from what one has come (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Kant's theory of geometry.Michael Friedman - 1985 - Philosophical Review 94 (4):455-506.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Mathematics in Kant's Critical Philosophy: Reflections on Mathematical Practice.Lisa Shabel - 2002 - New York: Routledge.
    This book provides a reading of Kant's theory of the construction of mathematical concepts through a fully contextualised analysis. In this work the author argues that it is only through an understanding of the relevant eighteenth century mathematics textbooks, and the related mathematical practice, that the material and context necessary for a successful interpretation of Kant's philosophy can be provided.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Human diagrammatic reasoning and seeing-as.Annalisa Coliva - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):121-148.
    The paper addresses the issue of human diagrammatic reasoning in the context of Euclidean geometry. It develops several philosophical categories which are useful for a description and an analysis of our experience while reasoning with diagrams. In particular, it draws the attention to the role of seeing-as; it analyzes its implications for proofs in Euclidean geometry and ventures the hypothesis that geometrical judgments are analytic and a priori, after all.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Diagrammatic Reasoning in Euclid’s Elements.Danielle Macbeth - 2010 - In Bart Van Kerkhove, Jean Paul Van Bendegem & Jonas De Vuyst (eds.), Philosophical Perspectives on Mathematical Practice. College Publications. pp. 235-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Constructive geometrical reasoning and diagrams.John Mumma - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):103-119.
    Modern formal accounts of the constructive nature of elementary geometry do not aim to capture the intuitive or concrete character of geometrical construction. In line with the general abstract approach of modern axiomatics, nothing is presumed of the objects that a geometric construction produces. This study explores the possibility of a formal account of geometric construction where the basic geometric objects are understood from the outset to possess certain spatial properties. The discussion is centered around Eu , a recently developed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Withering Away of Formal Semantics?Neil Tennant - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (4):302-318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics: A Study in Coginitive History. [REVIEW]Jenz Høyrup - 2005 - Studia Logica 80 (1):143-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • A Structural Account of Mathematics.Charles S. Chihara - 2003 - Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press UK.
    Charles Chihara's new book develops and defends a structural view of the nature of mathematics, and uses it to explain a number of striking features of mathematics that have puzzled philosophers for centuries. The view is used to show that, in order to understand how mathematical systems are applied in science and everyday life, it is not necessary to assume that its theorems either presuppose mathematical objects or are even true. Chihara builds upon his previous work, in which he presented (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • A Structural Account of Mathematics.Charles Chihara - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (1):79-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure of Euclid 's "Elements".Ian Mueller - 1983 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34 (1):57-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Mathematics in Kant's Critical Philosophy.Emily Carson & Lisa Shabel (eds.) - 2015 - Routledge.
    There is a long tradition, in the history and philosophy of science, of studying Kant’s philosophy of mathematics, but recently philosophers have begun to examine the way in which Kant’s reflections on mathematics play a role in his philosophy more generally, and in its development. For example, in the Critique of Pure Reason , Kant outlines the method of philosophy in general by contrasting it with the method of mathematics; in the Critique of Practical Reason , Kant compares the Formula (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • The logic of Euclidean construction procedures.P. Mäenpää & Jan von Plato - 1990 - Acta Philosophica Fennica 39:275-293.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the concept of proof in elementary geometry.Pirmin Stekeler-Weithofer - 1992 - In Michael Detlefsen (ed.), Proof and Knowledge in Mathematics. New York: Routledge. pp. 135--157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations