Switch to: Citations

References in:

Shifting Priorities: Simple Representations for Twenty-seven Iterated Theory Change Operators

In Jacek Malinowski David Makinson & Wansing Heinrich (eds.), Towards Mathematical Philosophy. Springer. pp. 269–296 (2009)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Method of Axiomatic Rejection for the Intuitionistic Propositional Logic.Rafal Dutkiewicz - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (4):449-459.
    We prove that the intuitionistic sentential calculus is Ł-decidable, i.e. the sets of these of Int and of rejected formulas are disjoint and their union is equal to all formulas. A formula is rejected iff it is a sentential variable or is obtained from other formulas by means of three rejection rules. One of the rules is original, the remaining two are Łukasiewicz's rejection rules: by detachement and by substitution. We extensively use the method of Beth's semantic tableaux.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The method of hypersequents in the proof theory of propositional non-classical logics.Arnon Avron - 1996 - In Wilfrid Hodges (ed.), Logic: Foundations to Applications. Oxford: pp. 1-32.
    Until not too many years ago, all logics except classical logic (and, perhaps, intuitionistic logic too) were considered to be things esoteric. Today this state of a airs seems to have completely been changed. There is a growing interest in many types of nonclassical logics: modal and temporal logics, substructural logics, paraconsistent logics, non-monotonic logics { the list is long. The diversity of systems that have been proposed and studied is so great that a need is felt by many researchers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   59 citations  
  • Some embedding theorems for modal logic.David Makinson - 1971 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 12 (2):252-254.
    Some results on the upper end of the lattice of all modal propositional logics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • On the logic of iterated belief revision.Adnan Darwiche & Judea Pearl - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 89 (1-2):1-29.
    We show in this paper that the AGM postulates are too weak to ensure the rational preservation of conditional beliefs during belief revision, thus permitting improper responses to sequences of observations. We remedy this weakness by proposing four additional postulates, which are sound relative to a qualitative version of probabilistic conditioning. Contrary to the AGM framework, the proposed postulates characterize belief revision as a process which may depend on elements of an epistemic state that are not necessarily captured by a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   141 citations  
  • Logics and Languages.M. J. Cresswell - 1973 - Synthese 40 (2):375-387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Categorial languages.M. J. Cresswell - 1977 - Studia Logica 36 (4):257 - 269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • On axiomatizability within a system.William Craig - 1953 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (1):30-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
  • Formal inconsistency and evolutionary databases.Walter A. Carnielli, João Marcos & Sandra De Amo - 2000 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 8 (2):115-152.
    This paper introduces new logical systems which axiomatize a formal representation of inconsistency (here taken to be equivalent to contradictoriness) in classical logic. We start from an intuitive semantical account of inconsistent data, fixing some basic requirements, and provide two distinct sound and complete axiomatics for such semantics, LFI1 and LFI2, as well as their first-order extensions, LFI1* and LFI2*, depending on which additional requirements are considered. These formal systems are examples of what we dub Logics of Formal Inconsistency (LFI) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • On the logic of small changes in hypertheories.John Cantwell - 1997 - Theoria 63 (1-2):54-89.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Iterated revision and minimal change of conditional beliefs.Craig Boutilier - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (3):263 - 305.
    We describe a model of iterated belief revision that extends the AGM theory of revision to account for the effect of a revision on the conditional beliefs of an agent. In particular, this model ensures that an agent makes as few changes as possible to the conditional component of its belief set. Adopting the Ramsey test, minimal conditional revision provides acceptance conditions for arbitrary right-nested conditionals. We show that problem of determining acceptance of any such nested conditional can be reduced (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • The lattice of modal logics: An algebraic investigation.W. J. Blok - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (2):221-236.
    Modal logics are studied in their algebraic disguise of varieties of so-called modal algebras. This enables us to apply strong results of a universal algebraic nature, notably those obtained by B. Jonsson. It is shown that the degree of incompleteness with respect to Kripke semantics of any modal logic containing the axiom □ p → p or containing an axiom of the form $\square^mp \leftrightarrow\square^{m + 1}p$ for some natural number m is 2 ℵ 0 . Furthermore, we show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • On syntactical categories.Yehoshua Bar-Hillel - 1950 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 15 (1):1-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Natural 3-valued logics—characterization and proof theory.Arnon Avron - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1):276-294.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   81 citations  
  • Explicit provability and constructive semantics.Sergei N. Artemov - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1):1-36.
    In 1933 Godel introduced a calculus of provability (also known as modal logic S4) and left open the question of its exact intended semantics. In this paper we give a solution to this problem. We find the logic LP of propositions and proofs and show that Godel's provability calculus is nothing but the forgetful projection of LP. This also achieves Godel's objective of defining intuitionistic propositional logic Int via classical proofs and provides a Brouwer-Heyting-Kolmogorov style provability semantics for Int which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   114 citations  
  • On the logic of theory change: Contraction functions and their associated revision functions.Carlos E. Alchourron & David Makinson - 1982 - Theoria 48 (1):14-37.
    A study in the logic of theory change, examining the properties of maxichoice contraction and revision operations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   108 citations  
  • Sprache und Sinn.Kasimir Ajdukiewicz - 1934 - Erkenntnis 4 (1):100-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • A comparison between lambek syntactic calculus and intuitionistic linear propositional logic.V. Michele Abrusci - 1990 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 36 (1):11-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The Complexity of Temporal Logic Model Checking.Ph Schoebelen - 1998 - In Marcus Kracht, Maarten de Rijke, Heinrich Wansing & Michael Zakharyaschev (eds.), Advances in Modal Logic. CSLI Publications. pp. 393-436.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic.Rudolf Carnap - 1947 - Chicago, IL, USA: University of Chicago Press.
    "This book is valuable as expounding in full a theory of meaning that has its roots in the work of Frege and has been of the widest influence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   687 citations  
  • Introduction to metamathematics.Stephen Cole Kleene - 1952 - Groningen: P. Noordhoff N.V..
    Stephen Cole Kleene was one of the greatest logicians of the twentieth century and this book is the influential textbook he wrote to teach the subject to the next generation. It was first published in 1952, some twenty years after the publication of Godel's paper on the incompleteness of arithmetic, which marked, if not the beginning of modern logic. The 1930s was a time of creativity and ferment in the subject, when the notion of computable moved from the realm of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   546 citations  
  • Mathematical Methods in Linguistics.Barbara Partee, Alice ter Meulen & Robert Wall - 1987 - Boston, MA, USA: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Elementary set theory accustoms the students to mathematical abstraction, includes the standard constructions of relations, functions, and orderings, and leads to a discussion of the various orders of infinity. The material on logic covers not only the standard statement logic and first-order predicate logic but includes an introduction to formal systems, axiomatization, and model theory. The section on algebra is presented with an emphasis on lattices as well as Boolean and Heyting algebras. Background for recent research in natural language semantics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • A Textbook of Belief Dynamics: Solutions to Exercises.Sven Ove Hansson - 1999 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    In the middle of the 1980s, logical tools were discovered that make it possible to model changes in belief and knowledge in entirely new ways. These logical tools turned out to be applicable both to human beliefs and to the contents of databases. This is the first textbook in this new area. It contains both discursive chapters with a minimum of formalism and formal chapters in which proofs and proof methods are presented. By using different selections from the formal section (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Frontiers of Belief Revision.M. Williams & Hans Rott (eds.) - 2001 - Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On reduction systems equivalent to the Lambek calculus with the empty string.Wojciech Zielonka - 2002 - Studia Logica 71 (1):31-46.
    The paper continues a series of results on cut-rule axiomatizability of the Lambek calculus. It provides a complete solution of a problem which was solved partially in one of the author''s earlier papers. It is proved that the product-free Lambek Calculus with the empty string (L 0) is not finitely axiomatizable if the only rule of inference admitted is Lambek''s cut rule. The proof makes use of the (infinitely) cut-rule axiomatized calculus C designed by the author exactly for this purpose.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cut-Rule Axiomatization of Product-Free Lambek Calculus With the Empty String.Wojciech Zielonka - 1988 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 34 (2):135-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cut-Rule Axiomatization of the Syntactic Calculus L0.Wojciech Zielonka - 2001 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10 (2):233-236.
    In Zielonka (1981a, 1989), I found an axiomatics for the product-free calculus L of Lambek whose only rule is the cut rule. Following Buszkowski (1987), we shall call such an axiomatics linear. It was proved that there is no finite axiomatics of that kind. In Lambek's original version of the calculus (cf. Lambek, 1958), sequent antecedents are non empty. By dropping this restriction, we obtain the variant L0 of L. This modification, introduced in the early 1980s (see, e.g., Buszkowski, 1985; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Axiomatizability of Ajdukiewicz‐Lambek Calculus by Means of Cancellation Schemes.Wojciech Zielonka - 1981 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 27 (13‐14):215-224.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Provability logics with quantifiers on proofs.Rostislav E. Yavorsky - 2001 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 113 (1-3):373-387.
    We study here extensions of the Artemov's logic of proofs in the language with quantifiers on proof variables. Since the provability operator □ A could be expressed in this language by the formula u[u]A, the corresponding logic naturally extends the well-known modal provability logic GL. Besides, the presence of quantifiers on proofs allows us to study some properties of provability not covered by the propositional logics.In this paper we study the arithmetical complexity of the provability logic with quantifiers on proofs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Logical and philosophical ideas in certain formal approaches to language.Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 1998 - Synthese 116 (2):231-277.
    This paper reminds, puts in order, sketches and also initiates some researches from the field of logic and philosophy of language. It lays emphasis on the logical-linguistic and ontological developmental lines originated with Polish researchers. The author discusses two opposite orientations of the former line in the process of formalization of language, called here nominalistic and Platonistic. The paper mentions the author's result (1989; 1991) concerning theoretical equivalence of two axiomatic approaches to language syntax which take into consideration these two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On the eliminatibility of ideal linguistic entities.Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 1989 - Studia Logica 48 (4):587 - 615.
    With reference to Polish logico-philosophical tradition two formal theories of language syntax have been sketched and then compared with each other. The first theory is based on the assumption that the basic linguistic stratum is constituted by object-tokens (concrete objects perceived through the senses) and that the types of such objects (ideal objects) are derivative constructs. The other is founded on an opposite philosophical orientation. The two theories are equivalent. The main conclusion is that in syntactic researches it is redundant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • On obligations and normative ability: Towards a logical analysis of the social contract.Michael Wooldridge & Wiebe van der Hoek - 2005 - Journal of Applied Logic 3 (3-4):396-420.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Social laws in alternating time: Effectiveness, feasibility, and synthesis.Wiebe van der Hoek, Mark Roberts & Michael Wooldridge - 2007 - Synthese 156 (1):1-19.
    Since it was first proposed by Moses, Shoham, and Tennenholtz, the social laws paradigm has proved to be one of the most compelling approaches to the offline coordination of multiagent systems. In this paper, we make four key contributions to the theory and practice of social laws in multiagent systems. First, we show that the Alternating-time Temporal Logic (atl) of Alur, Henzinger, and Kupferman provides an elegant and powerful framework within which to express and understand social laws for multiagent systems. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Essays in Logical Semantics.John Hawthorn - 1986 - Springer.
    Recent developments in the semantics of natural language seem to lead to a genuine synthesis of ideas from linguistics and logic, producing novel concepts and questions of interest to both parent disciplines. This book is a collection of essays on such new topics, which have arisen over the past few years. Taking a broad view, developments in formal semantics over the past decade can be seen as follows. At the beginning stands Montague's pioneering work, showing how a rigorous semantics can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Completeness of weak implication.Alasdair I. F. Urquhart - 1971 - Theoria 37 (3):274-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Minimal logic is adequate for Popperian science.Neil Tennant - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (3):325-329.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Some Useful 16-Valued Logics: How a Computer Network Should Think.Yaroslav Shramko & Heinrich Wansing - 2005 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (2):121-153.
    In Belnap's useful 4-valued logic, the set 2 = {T, F} of classical truth values is generalized to the set 4 = ������(2) = {Ø, {T}, {F}, {T, F}}. In the present paper, we argue in favor of extending this process to the set 16 = ᵍ (4) (and beyond). It turns out that this generalization is well-motivated and leads from the bilattice FOUR₂ with an information and a truth-and-falsity ordering to another algebraic structure, namely the trilattice SIXTEEN₃ with an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Hyper-contradictions, generalized truth values and logics of truth and falsehood.Yaroslav Shramko & Heinrich Wansing - 2006 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 15 (4):403-424.
    In Philosophical Logic, the Liar Paradox has been used to motivate the introduction of both truth value gaps and truth value gluts. Moreover, in the light of “revenge Liar” arguments, also higher-order combinations of generalized truth values have been suggested to account for so-called hyper-contradictions. In the present paper, Graham Priest's treatment of generalized truth values is scrutinized and compared with another strategy of generalizing the set of classical truth values and defining an entailment relation on the resulting sets of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • On the emergence of social conventions: modeling, analysis, and simulations.Yoav Shoham & Moshe Tennenholtz - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 94 (1-2):139-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Classical logic II: Higher-order logic.Stewart Shapiro - 2001 - In Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. pp. 33--54.
    A typical interpreted formal language has (first‐order) variables that range over a collection of objects, sometimes called a domain‐of‐discourse. The domain is what the formal language is about. A language may also contain second‐order variables that range over properties, sets, or relations on the items in the domain‐of‐discourse, or over functions from the domain to itself. For example, the sentence ‘Alexander has all the qualities of a great leader’ would naturally be rendered with a second‐order variable ranging over qualities. Similarly, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The modal logic of provability. The sequential approach.Giovanni Sambin & Silvio Valentini - 1982 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (3):311 - 342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Two methods of constructing contractions and revisions of knowledge systems.Hans Rott - 1991 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 20 (2):149 - 173.
    This paper investigates the formal relationship between two prominent approaches to the logic of belief change. The first one uses the idea of "relational partial meet contractions" as developed by Alchourrón, Gärdenfors and Makinson (Journal of Symbolic Logic 1985), the second one uses the concept of "epistemic entrenchment" as elaborated by Gärdenfors and Makinson (in Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Knowledge, M. Y. Vardi, Los Altos 1988). The two approaches are shown to be strictly equivalent via direct links between the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  • Stability, strength and sensitivity: Converting belief into knowledge.Hans Rott - 2004 - Erkenntnis 61 (2-3):469-493.
    In this paper I discuss the relation between various properties that have been regarded as important for determining whether or not a belief constitutes a piece of knowledge: its stability, strength and sensitivity to truth, as well as the strength of the epistemic position in which the subject is with respect to this belief. Attempts to explicate the relevant concepts more formally with the help of systems of spheres of possible worlds (à la Lewis and Grove) must take care to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Modellings for belief change: Prioritization and entrenchment.Hans Rott - 1992 - Theoria 58 (1):21-57.
    We distinguish the set of explicit beliefs of a reasoner, his "belief base", from the beliefs that are merely implicit. Syntax-based belief change governed by the structure of the belief base and the ranking ("prioritization") of its elements is reconstructed with the help of an epistemic entrenchment relation in the style of Gärdenfors and Makinson. Though priorities are essentially different from entrenchments, distinguished relations of epistemic entrenchment may be obtained from prioritized belief bases by a number of different constructions. An (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Ontology in the Tractatus of L. Wittgenstein.Roman Suszko - 1968 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 9 (1):7-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Knowledge, Belief and Counterfactual Reasoning in Games.Robert Stalnaker - 1996 - Economics and Philosophy 12 (2):133.
    Deliberation about what to do in any context requires reasoning about what will or would happen in various alternative situations, including situations that the agent knows will never in fact be realized. In contexts that involve two or more agents who have to take account of each others' deliberation, the counterfactual reasoning may become quite complex. When I deliberate, I have to consider not only what the causal effects would be of alternative choices that I might make, but also what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Splitting lattices of logics.Wolfgang Rautenberg - 1980 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 20 (3-4):155-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Contrary-to-duty obligations.Henry Prakken & Marek Sergot - 1996 - Studia Logica 57 (1):91 - 115.
    We investigate under what conditions contrary-to-duty (CTD) structures lacking temporal and action elements can be given a coherent reading. We argue, contrary to some recent proposals, that CTD is not an instance of defeasible reasoning, and that methods of nonmonotonic logics are inadequate since they are unable to distinguish between defeasibility and violation of primary obligations. We propose a semantic framework based on the idea that primary and CTD obligations are obligations of different kinds: a CTD obligation pertains to, or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • A cut-free simple sequent calculus for modal logic S5.Francesca Poggiolesi - 2008 - Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):3-15.
    In this paper, we present a simple sequent calculus for the modal propositional logic S5. We prove that this sequent calculus is theoremwise equivalent to the Hilbert-style system S5, that it is contraction-free and cut-free, and finally that it is decidable. All results are proved in a purely syntactic way.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Combinators and categorial grammar.Peter Simons - 1989 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 30 (2):241-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A geometric proof of the completeness of the łukasiewicz calculus.Giovanni Panti - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):563-578.
    We give a self-contained geometric proof of the completeness theorem for the infinite-valued sentential calculus of Łukasiewicz.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations