Switch to: Citations

References in:

Killing Kripkenstein's Monster

Noûs 54 (2):257-289 (2020)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Against Content Normativity.Kathrin Glüer & Åsa Wikforss - 2009 - Mind 118 (469):31-70.
    As meaning's claim to normativity has grown increasingly suspect the normativity thesis has shifted to mental content. In this paper, we distinguish two versions of content normativism: 'CE normativism', according to which it is essential to content that certain 'oughts' can be derived from it, and 'CD normativism', according to which content is determined by norms in the first place. We argue that neither type of normativism withstands scrutiny. CE normativism appeals to the fact that there is an essential connection (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  • Dispositions, rules, and finks.Toby Handfield & Alexander Bird - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 140 (2):285 - 298.
    This paper discusses the prospects of a dispositional solution to the Kripke–Wittgenstein rule-following puzzle. Recent attempts to employ dispositional approaches to this puzzle have appealed to the ideas of finks and antidotes—interfering dispositions and conditions—to explain why the rule-following disposition is not always manifested. We argue that this approach fails: agents cannot be supposed to have straightforward dispositions to follow a rule which are in some fashion masked by other, contrary dispositions of the agent, because in all cases, at least (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Dispositions and conditionals.C. B. Martin - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (174):1-8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   401 citations  
  • Putnam’s paradox.David Lewis - 1984 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3):221 – 236.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   417 citations  
  • Meaning and normativity.Allan Gibbard - 1994 - Philosophical Issues 5:95-115.
    The concepts of meaning and mental content resist naturalistic analysis. This is because they are normative: they depend on ideas of how things ought to be.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   148 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Wittgenstein's philosophy of mathematics.Michael Dummett - 1959 - Philosophical Review 68 (3):324-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   101 citations  
  • (1 other version)What the tortoise said to Achilles.Lewis Carroll - 1895 - Mind 4 (14):278-280.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   630 citations  
  • (1 other version)On misunderstanding Wittgenstein: Kripke's private language argument.Gordon P. Baker & P. M. S. Hacker - 1984 - Synthese 58 (3):407-450.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Does a rock implement every finite-state automaton?David J. Chalmers - 1996 - Synthese 108 (3):309-33.
    Hilary Putnam has argued that computational functionalism cannot serve as a foundation for the study of the mind, as every ordinary open physical system implements every finite-state automaton. I argue that Putnam's argument fails, but that it points out the need for a better understanding of the bridge between the theory of computation and the theory of physical systems: the relation of implementation. It also raises questions about the class of automata that can serve as a basis for understanding the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   147 citations  
  • How to speak of the colors.Mark Johnston - 1992 - Philosophical Studies 68 (3):221-263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   559 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Kripke on Wittgenstein on rules.Warren D. Goldfarb - 1982 - Journal of Philosophy 79 (September):471-488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • (1 other version)The rule-following considerations.Paul Boghossian - 1989 - Mind 98 (392):507-49.
    I. Recent years have witnessed a great resurgence of interest in the writings of the later Wittgenstein, especially with those passages roughly, Philosophical Investigations p)I 38 — 242 and Remarks on the Foundations of mathematics, section VI that are concerned with the topic of rules. Much of the credit for all this excitement, unparalleled since the heyday of Wittgenstein scholarship in the early IIJ6os, must go to Saul Kripke's I4rittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. It is easy to explain why. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   289 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Counterfactuals.David Lewis - 1973 - Foundations of Language 13 (1):145-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1279 citations  
  • (4 other versions)Philosophical investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein & G. E. M. Anscombe - 1953 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 161:124-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2911 citations  
  • Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories.Ruth Garrett Millikan - 1984 - Behaviorism 14 (1):51-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1712 citations  
  • Primitive Normativity and Skepticism about Rules.Hannah Ginsborg - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy 108 (5):227-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Does "belief holism" show that reductive dispositionalism about content could not be true?Alexander Miller - 2003 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1):73-90.
    Paul Boghossian has argued, on grounds concerning the holistic nature of belief fixation, that there are principled reasons for thinking that 'optimal conditions' versions of reductive dispositionalism about content cannot hope to satisfy a condition of extensional accuracy. I discern three separable strands of argument in Boghossian's work—the circularity objection, the open-endedness objection, and the certification objection—and argue that each of these objections fails. My conclusion is that for all that Boghossian has shown, 'optimal conditions' versions of reductive dispositionalism have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Normative Force of Promising.Jack Woods - 2016 - Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 6:77-101.
    Why do promises give rise to reasons? I consider a quadruple of possibilities which I think will not work, then sketch the explanation of the normativity of promising I find more plausible—that it is constitutive of the practice of promising that promise-breaking implies liability for blame and that we take liability for blame to be a bad thing. This effects a reduction of the normativity of promising to conventionalism about liability together with instrumental normativity and desire-based reasons. This is important (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • 1. Wittgenstein’s Conception of Grammar.Michael N. Forster - 2004 - In Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar. Princeton, NJ, USA: Princeton University Press. pp. 7-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Normativity in Reasoning.John Broome - 2014 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 95 (4):622-633.
    Reasoning is a process through which premise-attitudes give rise to a conclusion-attitude. When you reason actively you operate on the propositions that are the contents of your premise-attitudes, following a rule, to derive a new proposition that is the content of your conclusion-attitude. It may seem that, when you follow a rule, you must, at least implicitly, have the normative belief that you ought to comply with the rule, which guides you to comply. But I argue that to follow a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Grounding, transitivity, and contrastivity.Jonathan Schaffer - 2012 - In Fabrice Correia & Benjamin Schnieder (eds.), Metaphysical grounding: understanding the structure of reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 122-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   224 citations  
  • Rule-following, ideal conditions, and finkish dispositions.Andrea Guardo - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 157 (2):195-209.
    This paper employs some outcomes (for the most part due to David Lewis) of the contemporary debate on the metaphysics of dispositions to evaluate those dispositional analyses of meaning that make use of the concept of a disposition in ideal conditions. The first section of the paper explains why one may find appealing the notion of an ideal-condition dispositional analysis of meaning and argues that Saul Kripke’s well-known argument against such analyses is wanting. The second section focuses on Lewis’ work (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Models and reality.Hilary Putnam - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (3):464-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   292 citations  
  • Sense and prescriptivity.Kathrin Gluer - 1999 - Acta Analytica 14 (23):111-128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • (1 other version)Semantic normativity.Åsa Maria Wikforss - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 102 (2):203-26.
    My paper examines the popular idea, defended by Kripke, that meaning is an essentially normative notion. I consider four common versions of this idea and suggest that none of them can be supported, either because the alleged normativity has nothing to do with normativity or because it cannot plausibly be said that meaning is normative in the sense suggested. I argue that contrary to received opinion, we don’t need normativity to secure the possibility of meaning. I conclude by considering the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  • The dispositionalist solution to Wittgenstein's problem about understanding a rule: Answering Kripke's objection.Carl Ginet - 1992 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 17 (1):53-73.
    The paper explicates a version of dispositionalism and defends it against Kripke's objections (in his "Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language") that 1) it leaves out the normative aspect of a rule, 2) it cannot account for the directness of the knowledge one has of what one meant, and 3) regarding rules for computable functions of numbers, a) there are numbers beyond one's capacity to consider and b) there are people who are disposed to make systematic mistakes in computing values (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)The individual strikes back.Simon Blackburn - 1984 - Synthese 58 (March):281-302.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Précis of Vagueness.Timothy Williamson - 1997 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4):921-928.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   414 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Concept of Mind.Gilbert Ryle - 1949 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 141:125-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2257 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language.Christopher Peacocke - 1984 - Philosophical Review 93 (2):263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Vagueness.Loretta Torrago - 1998 - Philosophical Review 107 (4):637.
    Consider an object or property a and the predicate F. Then a is vague if there are questions of the form: Is a F? that have no yes-or-no answers. In brief, vague properties and kinds have borderline instances and composite objects have borderline constituents. I'll use the expression "borderline cases" as a covering term for both. ;Having borderline cases is compatible with precision so long as every case is either borderline F, determinately F or determinately not F. Thus, in addition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   147 citations  
  • Methodological reflections on current linguistic theory.W. V. Quine - 1970 - Synthese 21 (3-4):386-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   64 citations  
  • The social aspect of language.Donald Davidson - 1994 - In Brian F. McGuinness & Gianluigi Oliveri (eds.), The Philosophy of Michael Dummett. Dordrecht, Netherland: Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 1--16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • (2 other versions)On the Very idea of a Conceptual Scheme.Donald Davidson - 1984 - In Inquiries Into Truth And Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press. pp. 183-198.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   255 citations  
  • (1 other version)Models and reality.Hilary Putnam - 1983 - In Realism and reason. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 1-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Dispositional properties.A. D. Smith - 1977 - Mind 86 (343):439-445.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • (1 other version)Objective content.Miller Alexander - 2003 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1):73–90.
    [Alan Weir] This paper addresses the problem of how to account for objective content-for the distinction between how we actually apply terms and the conditions in which we ought to apply them-from within a naturalistic framework. Though behaviourist or dispositionalist approaches are generally held to be unsuccessful in naturalising objective content or 'normativity', I attempt to restore the credibility of such approaches by sketching a behaviouristic programme for explicating objective content. /// [Alexander Miller] Paul Boghossian (1989, 1990) has argued, on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Naturalizing content.Paul Boghossian - 1990 - In Barry M. Loewer (ed.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics. Cambridge: Blackwell.
    The conviction that intentional realism requires intentional reductionism has the philosophy of mind in its grip. Thus, Jerry Fodor: .... It is worth noting — if only because it so seldom is nowadays — that this rationale for the naturalistic conviction begs a question that doesn't obviously deserve to be begged. Why, indeed, must we think that no property can be real unless it is identical with, or supervenient upon, the properties that appear in the catalogues provided by physics? There (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Counterfactuals.David Lewis - 1973 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 36 (3):602-605.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1315 citations  
  • Wittgenstein on rules and private language.Saul A. Kripke - 1982 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 173 (4):496-499.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   989 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Counterfactuals.David Lewis - 1973 - Philosophy of Science 42 (3):341-344.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1160 citations  
  • Kripke’s Account of the Argument Against Private Language.Crispin Wright - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (12):759.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • (1 other version)Boghossian on Reductive Dispositionalism About Content: The Case Strengthened.Alexander Miller - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):1-10.
    Paul Boghossian has recently argued against reductive dispositionalism concerning mental content. However, there is a powerful version of reductive dispositionalism—based on work by Ramsey and Lewis—that Boghossian does not consider. In this paper I argue that Boghossian's arguments can be adapted to apply even to this stronger version of reductionism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Intentional Stance by Daniel Dennett. [REVIEW]Sydney Shoemaker - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy 87 (4):212-216.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   371 citations  
  • Is meaning normative?Anandi Hattiangadi - 2006 - Mind and Language 21 (2):220-240.
    Many people claim that semantic content is normative, and that therefore naturalistic theories of content face a potentially insuperable difficulty. The normativity of content allegedly undermines naturalism by introducing a gap between semantic 'ought's and the explanatory resources of naturalism. I argue here that this problem is not ultimately pressing for naturalists. The normativity thesis, I maintain, is ambiguous; it could mean either that the content of a term prescribes a pattern of use, or that it merely determines which pattern (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • (1 other version)Norms, history, and the mental.Fred Dretske - 2001 - In D. Walsh (ed.), Evolution, Naturalism and Mind. Cambridge University Press. pp. 87-104.
    Many people think the mind evolved. Some of them think it had to evolve. They think the mind not only has a history, but a history essential to its very existence.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics.Cora Diamond - 1981 - Philosophical Quarterly 31 (125):352-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Michael N. Forster, Wittgenstein on the Arbitrariness of Grammar. [REVIEW]John Hyman - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (3):471-473.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Representation and Reality.Robert Stalnaker - 1992 - Philosophical Review 101 (2):359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   249 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics.Michael Dummett - 1997 - Journal of Philosophy 94 (7):166--85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations