Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The logical basis of metaphysics.Michael Dummett - 1991 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    Such a conception, says Dummett, will form "a base camp for an assault on the metaphysical peaks: I have no greater ambition in this book than to set up a base ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   588 citations  
  • The foundations of arithmetic.Gottlob Frege - 1884/1950 - Evanston, Ill.,: Northwestern University Press.
    In arithmetic, if only because many of its methods and concepts originated in India, it has been the tradition to reason less strictly than in geometry, ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   441 citations  
  • What are logical notions?Alfred Tarski - 1986 - History and Philosophy of Logic 7 (2):143-154.
    In this manuscript, published here for the first time, Tarski explores the concept of logical notion. He draws on Klein's Erlanger Programm to locate the logical notions of ordinary geometry as those invariant under all transformations of space. Generalizing, he explicates the concept of logical notion of an arbitrary discipline.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   238 citations  
  • (1 other version)To be is to be a value of a variable (or to be some values of some variables).George Boolos - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (8):430-449.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   303 citations  
  • Quantifiers in Language and Logic.Stanley Peters & Dag Westerståhl - 2006 - Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Quantification is a topic which brings together linguistics, logic, and philosophy. Quantifiers are the essential tools with which, in language or logic, we refer to quantity of things or amount of stuff. In English they include such expressions as no, some, all, both, many. Peters and Westerstahl present the definitive interdisciplinary exploration of how they work - their syntax, semantics, and inferential role.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • The Logical Basis of Metaphysics.Michael Dummett, Hilary Putnam & James Conant - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (177):519-527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   276 citations  
  • The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint.Gila Sher - 1991 - MIT Press.
    The Bounds of Logic presents a new philosophical theory of the scope and nature of logic based on critical analysis of the principles underlying modern Tarskian logic and inspired by mathematical and linguistic development. Extracting central philosophical ideas from Tarski’s early work in semantics, Sher questions whether these are fully realized by the standard first-order system. The answer lays the foundation for a new, broader conception of logic. By generally characterizing logical terms, Sher establishes a fundamental result in semantics. Her (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   95 citations  
  • Reasoning with arbitrary objects.Kit Fine - 1985 - New York, NY, USA: Blackwell.
    Contents: Preface VII; Introduction 1; 1. The General Framework 5; 2. Some Standard Systems 61; 3. Systems in General 147; 4. Non-Standard Systems 177; Bibliography 210; General Index 215; Index of Symbols 219-220.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • The limits of abstraction.Kit Fine - 2002 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Matthias Schirn.
    Kit Fine develops a Fregean theory of abstraction, and suggests that it may yield a new philosophical foundation for mathematics, one that can account for both our reference to various mathematical objects and our knowledge of various mathematical truths. The Limits ofion breaks new ground both technically and philosophically.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   90 citations  
  • First order predicate logic with generalized quantifiers.Per Lindström - 1966 - Theoria 32 (3):186--195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   205 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Concept of Logical Consequence.John Etchemendy - 1994 - Erkenntnis 41 (2):281-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   154 citations  
  • Arbitrary reference.Wylie Breckenridge & Ofra Magidor - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 158 (3):377-400.
    Two fundamental rules of reasoning are Universal Generalisation and Existential Instantiation. Applications of these rules involve stipulations such as ‘Let n be an arbitrary number’ or ‘Let John be an arbitrary Frenchman’. Yet the semantics underlying such stipulations are far from clear. What, for example, does ‘n’ refer to following the stipulation that n be an arbitrary number? In this paper, we argue that ‘n’ refers to a number—an ordinary, particular number such as 58 or 2,345,043. Which one? We do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • A Formalization of Set Theory Without Variables.István Németi - 1988 - American Mathematical Soc..
    Completed in 1983, this work culminates nearly half a century of the late Alfred Tarski's foundational studies in logic, mathematics, and the philosophy of science. Written in collaboration with Steven Givant, the book appeals to a very broad audience, and requires only a familiarity with first-order logic. It is of great interest to logicians and mathematicians interested in the foundations of mathematics, but also to philosophers interested in logic, semantics, algebraic logic, or the methodology of the deductive sciences, and to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Referential and quantificational indefinites.Janet Dean Fodor & Ivan A. Sag - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (3):355 - 398.
    The formal semantics that we have proposed for definite and indefinite descriptions analyzes them both as variable-binding operators and as referring terms. It is the referential analysis which makes it possible to account for the facts outlined in Section 2, e.g. for the purely ‘instrumental’ role of the descriptive content; for the appearance of unusually wide scope readings relative to other quantifiers, higher predicates, and island boundaries; for the fact that the island-escaping readings are always equivalent to maximally wide scope (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Logicality and Invariance.Denis Bonnay - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):29-68.
    What is a logical constant? The question is addressed in the tradition of Tarski's definition of logical operations as operations which are invariant under permutation. The paper introduces a general setting in which invariance criteria for logical operations can be compared and argues for invariance under potential isomorphism as the most natural characterization of logical operations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The Bounds of Logic: A Generalized Viewpoint.Gila Sher - 1991 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (4):1078-1083.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  • Logical operations.Vann McGee - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 (6):567 - 580.
    Tarski and Mautner proposed to characterize the "logical" operations on a given domain as those invariant under arbitrary permutations. These operations are the ones that can be obtained as combinations of the operations on the following list: identity; substitution of variables; negation; finite or infinite disjunction; and existential quantification with respect to a finite or infinite block of variables. Inasmuch as every operation on this list is intuitively "logical", this lends support to the Tarski-Mautner proposal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • (1 other version)To Be is to be a Value of a Variable.George Boolos - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (2):616-617.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Scope or Pseudo scope? Are there Wide-Scope Indefinites?A. Kratzer - 1998 - In ¸ Iterothstein2001. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 163-196.
    The paper investigates the scope properties of indefinites.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Reasoning with Arbitrary Objects.Kit Fine - 1985 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 176 (3):402-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Limits of Abstraction.Kit Fine - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):554-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • Logical constants as punctuation marks.Kosta Došen - 1989 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 30 (3):362-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • Logic, Logics, and Logicism.Solomon Feferman - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (1):31-54.
    The paper starts with an examination and critique of Tarski’s wellknown proposed explication of the notion of logical operation in the type structure over a given domain of individuals as one which is invariant with respect to arbitrary permutations of the domain. The class of such operations has been characterized by McGee as exactly those definable in the language L∞,∞. Also characterized similarly is a natural generalization of Tarski’s thesis, due to Sher, in terms of bijections between domains. My main (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • The concept of logical consequence.William H. Hanson - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (3):365-409.
    In the first section, I consider what several logicians say informally about the notion of logical consequence. There is significant variation among these accounts, they are sometimes poorly explained, and some of them are clearly at odds with the usual technical definition. In the second section, I first argue that a certain kind of informal account—one that includes elements of necessity, generality, and apriority—is approximately correct. Next I refine this account and consider several important questions about it, including the appropriate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • (1 other version)Is Hume's principle analytic?G. Boolos - 1998 - Logic, Logic, and Logic:301--314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • (1 other version)The Limits of Abstraction.Kit Fine - 1998 - In Matthias Schirn, The Philosophy of Mathematics Today: Papers From a Conference Held in Munich From June 28 to July 4,1993. Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Abstraction and identity.Roy T. Cook & Philip A. Ebert - 2005 - Dialectica 59 (2):121–139.
    A co-authored article with Roy T. Cook forthcoming in a special edition on the Caesar Problem of the journal Dialectica. We argue against the appeal to equivalence classes in resolving the Caesar Problem.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Existence and description in formal logic.Dana Scott - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (1):181--200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Reasoning with Arbitrary Objects.John Macnamara - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):305.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  • Notions of Invariance for Abstraction Principles.G. A. Antonelli - 2010 - Philosophia Mathematica 18 (3):276-292.
    The logical status of abstraction principles, and especially Hume’s Principle, has been long debated, but the best currently availeble tool for explicating a notion’s logical character—permutation invariance—has not received a lot of attention in this debate. This paper aims to fill this gap. After characterizing abstraction principles as particular mappings from the subsets of a domain into that domain and exploring some of their properties, the paper introduces several distinct notions of permutation invariance for such principles, assessing the philosophical significance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • Fixed- versus Variable-domain Interpretations of Tarski’s Account of Logical Consequence.Paolo Mancosu - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (9):745-759.
    In this article I describe and evaluate the debate that surrounds the proper interpretation of Tarski’s account of logical consequence given in his classic 1936 article ‘On the concept of logical consequence’. In the late 1980s Etchemendy argued that the familiar model theoretic account of logical consequence is not to be found in Tarski’s original article. Whereas the contemporary account of logical consequence is a variable‐domain conception – in that it calls for a reinterpretation of the domain of variation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Variable Binding Term Operators.John Corcoran, William Hatcher & John Herring - 1972 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 18 (12):177-182.
    Chapin reviewed this 1972 ZEITSCHRIFT paper that proves the completeness theorem for the logic of variable-binding-term operators created by Corcoran and his student John Herring in the 1971 LOGIQUE ET ANALYSE paper in which the theorem was conjectured. This leveraging proof extends completeness of ordinary first-order logic to the extension with vbtos. Newton da Costa independently proved the same theorem about the same time using a Henkin-type proof. This 1972 paper builds on the 1971 “Notes on a Semantic Analysis of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A note on formality and logical consequence.Mario Gómez-Torrente - 2000 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (5):529-539.
    Logic is formal in the sense that all arguments of the same form as logically valid arguments are also logically valid and hence truth-preserving. However, it is not known whether all arguments that are valid in the usual model-theoretic sense are truthpreserving. Tarski claimed that it could be proved that all arguments that are valid (in the sense of validity he contemplated in his 1936 paper on logical consequence) are truthpreserving. But he did not offer the proof. The question arises (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Natural deduction and Hilbert's ɛ-operator.Allen Hazen - 1987 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 16 (4):411 - 421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Axioms for abstract model theory.K. J. Barwise - 1974 - Annals of Mathematical Logic 7 (2-3):221-265.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Quantifier scope: How labor is divided between QR and choice functions. [REVIEW]Tanya Reinhart - 1997 - Linguistics and Philosophy 20 (4):335-397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Proof theory and meaning: The context of deducibility.Greg Restall - 2010 - In Françoise Delon, Ulrich Kohlenbach, Penelope Maddy & Frank Stephan, Logic Colloquium 2007. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 204-219.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An Extension of Klein's Erlanger Program: Logic as Invariant-Theory.F. I. Mautner - 1946 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 11 (4):134-136.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations