Switch to: Citations

References in:

Constructivism in Ethics

New York: Cambridge University Press (2013)

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Is truth a goal of enquiry? Davidson vs. Wright.Richard Rorty - 1995 - Philosophical Quarterly 45 (180):281-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   70 citations  
  • “How to Be a Moral Realist.Richard Boyd - 1988 - In G. Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral Realism. Cornell University Press. pp. 181-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   510 citations  
  • Philosophical Investigations.Ludwig Wittgenstein - 1953 - New York, NY, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. Edited by G. E. M. Anscombe.
    Editorial preface to the fourth edition and modified translation -- The text of the Philosophische Untersuchungen -- Philosophische untersuchungen = Philosophical investigations -- Philosophie der psychologie, ein fragment = Philosophy of psychology, a fragment.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2253 citations  
  • Propositions about Reasons.John Skorupski - 2006 - European Journal of Philosophy 14 (1):26-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Propositions about reasons.John Skorupski - 2006 - European Journal of Philosophy 14 (1):26–48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Metaphysical pluralism.Huw Price - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy 89 (8):387-409.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Metaphysical Pluralism.Huw Price - 1992 - Journal of Philosophy 89 (8):387.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Why be rational.Niko Kolodny - 2005 - Mind 114 (455):509-563.
    Normativity involves two kinds of relation. On the one hand, there is the relation of being a reason for. This is a relation between a fact and an attitude. On the other hand, there are relations specified by requirements of rationality. These are relations among a person's attitudes, viewed in abstraction from the reasons for them. I ask how the normativity of rationality—the sense in which we ‘ought’ to comply with requirements of rationality—is related to the normativity of reasons—the sense (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   501 citations  
  • Second-Hand Moral Knowledge.Karen Jones - 1999 - Journal of Philosophy 96 (2):55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Second-hand moral knowledge.Karen Jones - 1999 - Journal of Philosophy 96 (2):55-78.
    Trust enters into the making of a virtuous person in at least two ways. First, unless a child has a sufficiently trusting relationship with at least one adult, it is doubtful that she will be able to become the kind of person who can form ethically responsible relationships with others. Infant trust, as Annette Baier has reminded us, is the foundation on which future trust relationships will be built; and when such trust is irreparably shaken, the adult into whom the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Normative Strength and the Balance of Reasons.Joshua Gert - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (4):533-562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Normative strength and the balance of reasons.Joshua Gert - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (4):533-562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Expressivism and language learning.Joshua Gert - 2002 - Ethics 112 (2):292-314.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Meta‐Ethics and The Problem of Creeping Minimalism.James Dreier - 2004 - Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1):23-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism.W. Child - 2001 - Mind 110 (439):721-725.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • The Possibility of Practical Reason.J. David Velleman - 1996 - Ethics 106 (4):694-726.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   359 citations  
  • Does rationality give us reasons?John Broome - 2005 - Philosophical Issues 15 (1):321–337.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   104 citations  
  • Reference explained away.Robert Brandom - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (9):469-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Reference Explained Away.Robert Brandom - 1984 - Journal of Philosophy 81 (9):469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Holism, Hyper‐analyticity and Hyper‐compositionality.Ned Block - 2007 - Mind and Language 8 (1):1-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Conceptual role semantics.Gilbert Harman - 1982 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (April):242-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   135 citations  
  • Conceptual role semantics.Gilbert Harman - 1982 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23:242-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   133 citations  
  • Does expressivism have subjectivist consequences?Mark Schroeder - 2014 - Philosophical Perspectives 28 (1):278-290.
    Metaethical expressivists claim that we can explain what moral words like ‘wrong’ mean without having to know what they are about – but rather by saying what it is to think that something is wrong – namely, to disapprove of it. Given the close connection between expressivists’ theory of the meaning of moral words and our attitudes of approval and disapproval, expressivists have had a hard time shaking the intuitive charge that theirs is an objectionably subjectivist or mind-dependent view of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Buck-passers' negative thesis.Mark Schroeder - 2009 - Philosophical Explorations 12 (3):341-347.
    Buck-passers about value accept two theses about value, a negative thesis and a positive. The negative thesis is that the fact that something is valuable is not itself a reason to promote or appreciate it. The positive thesis is that the fact that something is valuable consists in the fact that there are other reasons to promote or appreciate it. Buck-passers suppose that the negative thesis follows from the positive one, and sometimes insist on it as if it is the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Hybrid Expressivism: Virtues and Vices.Mark Schroeder - 2009 - Ethics 119 (2):257-309.
    This paper is a survey of recent ‘hybrid’ approaches to metaethics, according to which moral sentences, in some sense or other, express both beliefs and desires. I try to show what kinds of theoretical issues come up at the different choice points we encounter in developing such a view, to raise some problems and explain where they come from, and to begin to get a sense for what the payoff of such views can be, and what they will need to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Means-end coherence, stringency, and subjective reasons.Mark Schroeder - 2009 - Philosophical Studies 143 (2):223 - 248.
    Intentions matter. They have some kind of normative impact on our agency. Something goes wrong when an agent intends some end and fails to carry out the means she believes to be necessary for it, and something goes right when, intending the end, she adopts the means she thinks are required. This has even been claimed to be one of the only uncontroversial truths in ethical theory. But not only is there widespread disagreement about why this is so, there is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • Cudworth and Normative Explanations.Mark Schroeder - 2005 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 1 (3):1-28.
    Moral theories usually aspire to be explanatory – to tell us why something is wrong, why it is good, or why you ought to do it. So it is worth knowing how moral explanations differ, if they do, from explanations of other things. This paper uncovers a common unarticulated theory about how normative explanations must work – that they must follow what I call the Standard Model. Though the Standard Model Theory has many implications, in this paper I focus primarily (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Values and Secondary Qualities.John McDowell - 1985 - In Ted Honderich (ed.), Morality and objectivity: a tribute to J.L. Mackie. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul. pp. 110-129.
    J.L. Mackie insists that ordinary evaluative thought presents itself as a matter of sensitivity to aspects of the world. And this phenomenological thesis seems correct. When one or another variety of philosophical non-cognitivism claims to capture the truth about what the experience of value is like, or (in a familiar surrogate for phenomenology) about what we mean by our evaluative language, the claim is never based on careful attention to the lived character of evaluative thought or discourse. The idea is, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   334 citations  
  • Foundations of Social Theory.James Samuel Coleman - 1990 - Belknap Press.
    Combining principles of individual rational choice with a sociological conception of collective action, James Coleman recasts social theory in a bold new way. The result is a landmark in sociological theory, capable of describing both stability and change in social systems. This book provides for the first time a sound theoretical foundation for linking the behavior of individuals to organizational behavior and then to society as a whole. The power of the theory is especially apparent when Coleman analyzes corporate actors, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   415 citations  
  • Knowledge, Understanding and Epistemic Value.Duncan Pritchard - 2009 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64:19-43.
    It is argued that a popular way of accounting for the distinctive value of knowledge by appeal to the distinctive value of cognitive achievements fails because it is a mistake to identify knowledge with cognitive achievements. Nevertheless, it is claimed that understanding, properly conceived, is a type of cognitive achievement, and thus that the distinctive value of cognitive achievements can explain why understanding is of special value.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Normative Properties.Allan Gibbard - 2003 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1):141-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Supervenience.Brian McLaughlin - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Response‐Dependence and Normative Bedrock.Joshua Gert - 2009 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (3):718-742.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Review of Woodward, Making Things Happen. [REVIEW]Michael Strevens - 2007 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (1):233-249.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   601 citations  
  • Naturalism and the Fate of the M-Worlds.Huw Price & Frank Jackson - 1997 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 71:247-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Robert B. Brandom, Articulating Reasons (An Introduction to Inferentialism). [REVIEW]Robert B. Brandom - 2001 - Erkenntnis 55 (1):121-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   260 citations  
  • Value, reasons and the structure of justification: how to avoid passing the buck.R. Crisp - 2005 - Analysis 65 (1):80-85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Aesthetic/sensory Dependence.Nick Zangwill - 1998 - British Journal of Aesthetics 38 (1):66-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Scepticism and Dreaming: Imploding The Demon.Crispin Wright - 1991 - Noûs 25 (2):205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  • Ralph Wedgwood, The Nature of Normativity: Clarendon Press, Oxford, 2007, p. 296, ISBN-13:9780199251315. £35.00. [REVIEW]Chris Alen Sula - 2008 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (2):227-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  • Quietism.Nick Zangwill - 1992 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 17 (1):160-176.
    Metaphysics-—the enquiry into the constitution of reality-seems like the very crown of philosophy. What could be more exciting, more important, and more substantive than the pursuit of such a discipline? The majority of philosophers have been content to assume that metaphysics is a viable enterprise; they have held various metaphysical views and engaged in metaphysical arguments. But there has always been a small but persistent maverick minority of philosophers who have cast aspersions on the whole undertaking. Metaphysics, they tell us, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Rules, Reasons and Norms.Philip Pettit - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 124 (2):185-197.
    Philip Pettit has drawn together here a series of interconnected essays on three subjects to which he has made notable contributions. The first part of the book discusses the rule-following character of thought. The second considers how choice can be responsive to different sorts of factors, while still being under the control of thought and the reasons that thought marshals. The third examines the implications of this view of choice and rationality for the normative regulation of social behaviour. Rules, Reasons, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Scepticism and dreaming: Imploding the demon.Crispin Wright - 1991 - Noûs 25 (2):205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   92 citations  
  • Review of M aking Things Happen. [REVIEW]Eric Hiddleston - 2005 - Philosophical Review 114 (4):545-547.
    Woodward's long awaited book is an attempt to construct a comprehensive account of causation explanation that applies to a wide variety of causal and explanatory claims in different areas of science and everyday life. The book engages some of the relevant literature from other disciplines, as Woodward weaves together examples, counterexamples, criticisms, defences, objections, and replies into a convincing defence of the core of his theory, which is that we can analyse causation by appeal to the notion of manipulation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   314 citations  
  • Works and Worlds of Art.George Dickie - 1983 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (2):279-281.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Buck-passing and the right kind of reasons.Wlodek Rabinowicz & Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen - 2006 - Philosophical Quarterly 56 (222):114–120.
    The ‘buck-passing’ account equates the value of an object with the existence of reasons to favour it. As we argued in an earlier paper, this analysis faces the ‘wrong kind of reasons’ problem: there may be reasons for pro-attitudes towards worthless objects, in particular if it is the pro-attitudes, rather than their objects, that are valuable. Jonas Olson has recently suggested how to resolve this difficulty: a reason to favour an object is of the right kind only if its formulation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy.Bernard Williams - 1987 - Behaviorism 15 (2):179-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   535 citations  
  • Review of E thics and the Limits of Philosophy.Thomas Nagel - 1986 - Journal of Philosophy 83 (6):351-360.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   180 citations  
  • The aim of belief.Ralph Wedgwood - 2002 - Philosophical Perspectives 16:267-97.
    It is often said, metaphorically, that belief "aims" at the truth. This paper proposes a normative interpretation of this metaphor. First, the notion of "epistemic norms" is clarified, and reasons are given for the view that epistemic norms articulate essential features of the beliefs that are subject to them. Then it is argued that all epistemic norms--including those that specify when beliefs count as rational, and when they count as knowledge--are explained by a fundamental norm of correct belief, which requires (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   360 citations  
  • The metaethicists' mistake.Ralph Wedgwood - 2004 - Philosophical Perspectives 18 (1):405–426.
    According to normative judgment internalism (NJI), normative judgments -- that is, judgments of the form 'I ought to F' and the like -- are "essentially practical", in the sense that they are in some way essentially connected to practical reasoning, or to motivation for action. Many metaethicists believe that if NJI is true, then it would cast grave doubts on any robustly realist (RR) conception of normative judgments. These metaethicists are mistaken. This mistake about the relations between NJI and RR (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations