Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. Proper classes.Penelope Maddy - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (1):113-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Passion and Value in Hume's Treatise.D. G. C. Macnabb - 1968 - Philosophical Books 9 (1):2-4.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • The potential hierarchy of sets.Øystein Linnebo - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (2):205-228.
    Some reasons to regard the cumulative hierarchy of sets as potential rather than actual are discussed. Motivated by this, a modal set theory is developed which encapsulates this potentialist conception. The resulting theory is equi-interpretable with Zermelo Fraenkel set theory but sheds new light on the set-theoretic paradoxes and the foundations of set theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   97 citations  
  • Pluralities and Sets.Øystein Linnebo - 2010 - Journal of Philosophy 107 (3):144-164.
    Say that some things form a set just in case there is a set whose members are precisely the things in question. For instance, all the inhabitants of New York form a set. So do all the stars in the universe. And so do all the natural numbers. Under what conditions do some things form a set?
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Generality Explained.Øystein Linnebo - 2022 - Journal of Philosophy 119 (7):349-379.
    What explains the truth of a universal generalization? Two types of explanation can be distinguished. While an ‘instance-based explanation’ proceeds via some or all instances of the generalization, a ‘generic explanation’ is independent of the instances, relying instead on completely general facts about the properties or operations involved in the generalization. This intuitive distinction is analyzed by means of a truthmaker semantics, which also sheds light on the correct logic of quantification. On the most natural version of the semantics, this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Dummett on Indefinite Extensibility.Øystein Linnebo - 2018 - Philosophical Issues 28 (1):196-220.
    Dummett’s notion of indefinite extensibility is influential but obscure. The notion figures centrally in an alternative Dummettian argument for intuitionistic logic and anti-realism, distinct from his more famous, meaning-theoretic arguments to the same effect. Drawing on ideas from Dummett, a precise analysis of indefinite extensibility is proposed. This analysis is used to reconstruct the poorly understood alternative argument. The plausibility of the resulting argument is assessed.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Actual and Potential Infinity.Øystein Linnebo & Stewart Shapiro - 2017 - Noûs 53 (1):160-191.
    The notion of potential infinity dominated in mathematical thinking about infinity from Aristotle until Cantor. The coherence and philosophical importance of the notion are defended. Particular attention is paid to the question of whether potential infinity is compatible with classical logic or requires a weaker logic, perhaps intuitionistic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • On the interpretation of intuitionistic number theory.S. C. Kleene - 1945 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 10 (4):109-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • Predicativity and Feferman.Laura Crosilla - 2017 - In Gerhard Jäger & Wilfried Sieg (eds.), Feferman on Foundations: Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy. Cham: Springer. pp. 423-447.
    Predicativity is a notable example of fruitful interaction between philosophy and mathematical logic. It originated at the beginning of the 20th century from methodological and philosophical reflections on a changing concept of set. A clarification of this notion has prompted the development of fundamental new technical instruments, from Russell's type theory to an important chapter in proof theory, which saw the decisive involvement of Kreisel, Feferman and Schütte. The technical outcomes of predica-tivity have since taken a life of their own, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Metaphysics. Aristotle - 1941 - In Ross W. D. (ed.), The Basic Works of Aristotle. Random House.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   170 citations  
  • Quantification and realism.Michael Glanzberg - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (3):541–572.
    This paper argues for the thesis that, roughly put, it is impossible to talk about absolutely everything. To put the thesis more precisely, there is a particular sense in which, as a matter of semantics, quantifiers always range over domains that are in principle extensible, and so cannot count as really being ‘absolutely everything’. The paper presents an argument for this thesis, and considers some important objections to the argument and to the formulation of the thesis. The paper also offers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Quantification and Realism.Michael Glanzberg - 2004 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (3):541-572.
    This paper argues for the thesis that, roughly put, it is impossible to talk about absolutely everything. To put the thesis more precisely, there is a particular sense in which, as a matter of semantics, quantifiers always range over domains that are in principle extensible, and so cannot count as really being ‘absolutely everything’. The paper presents an argument for this thesis, and considers some important objections to the argument and to the formulation of the thesis. The paper also offers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Intuition between the analytic-continental divide: Hermann Weyl's philosophy of the continuum.Janet Folina - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (1):25-55.
    Though logical positivism is part of Kant's complex legacy, positivists rejected both Kant's theory of intuition and his classification of mathematical knowledge as synthetic a priori. This paper considers some lingering defenses of intuition in mathematics during the early part of the twentieth century, as logical positivism was born. In particular, it focuses on the difficult and changing views of Hermann Weyl about the proper role of intuition in mathematics. I argue that it was not intuition in general, but his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Our Knowledge of Mathematical Objects.Kit Fine - 2005 - In Tamar Szabó Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 89-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Our knowledge of mathematical objects.Kit Fine - 2005 - In Tamar Szabó Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 89-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Traditional logic and the early history of sets, 1854-1908.José Ferreirós - 1996 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 50 (1):5-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Systems of predicative analysis.Solomon Feferman - 1964 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 29 (1):1-30.
    This paper is divided into two parts. Part I provides a resumé of the evolution of the notion of predicativity. Part II describes our own work on the subject.Part I§1. Conceptions of sets.Statements about sets lie at the heart of most modern attempts to systematize all (or, at least, all known) mathematics. Technical and philosophical discussions concerning such systematizations and the underlying conceptions have thus occupied a considerable portion of the literature on the foundations of mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   117 citations  
  • Predicativity.Solomon Feferman - 2005 - In Stewart Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter is a detailed study of predicativity in mathematics. It presents a number of historical versions predicativity requirements, looking for unifying ideas. The further development of the notions and requirements up to the present is traced, articulating connections among the different ideas. One underlying theme of the chapter is the motivations for the various requirements for rejecting impredicativity and the various ways of stating the requirement.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • From Kant to Hilbert: a source book in the foundations of mathematics.William Bragg Ewald (ed.) - 1996 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This massive two-volume reference presents a comprehensive selection of the most important works on the foundations of mathematics. While the volumes include important forerunners like Berkeley, MacLaurin, and D'Alembert, as well as such followers as Hilbert and Bourbaki, their emphasis is on the mathematical and philosophical developments of the nineteenth century. Besides reproducing reliable English translations of classics works by Bolzano, Riemann, Hamilton, Dedekind, and Poincare, William Ewald also includes selections from Gauss, Cantor, Kronecker, and Zermelo, all translated here for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Mathematics in Philosophy.Charles Parsons - 1987 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 177 (1):88-90.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Mathematics without foundations.Hilary Putnam - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (1):5-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   139 citations  
  • Philosophy of mathematics, selected readings.Paul Benacerraf & Hilary Putnam - 1966 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 156:501-502.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Mathematics in Philosophy.Charles Parsons - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (4):588-606.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Weyl Reexamined: “Das Kontinuum” 100 Years Later.Arnon Avron - 2020 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 26 (1):26-79.
    Hermann Weyl was one of the greatest mathematicians of the 20th century, with contributions to many branches of mathematics and physics. In 1918 he wrote a famous book, “Das Kontinuum”, on the foundations of mathematics. In that book he described mathematical analysis as a ‘house built on sand’, and tried to ‘replace this shifting foundation with pillars of enduring strength’. In this paper we reexamine and explain the philosophical and mathematical ideas that underly Weyl’s system in “Das Kontinuum”, and show (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Brouwer and Weyl: The Phenomenology and Mathematics of the Intuitive Continuum.Mark Atten, Dirk Dalen & Richard Tieszen - 2002 - Philosophia Mathematica 10 (2):203-226.
    Brouwer and Weyl recognized that the intuitive continuum requires a mathematical analysis of a kind that set theory is not able to provide. As an alternative, Brouwer introduced choice sequences. We first describe the features of the intuitive continuum that prompted this development, focusing in particular on the flow of internal time as described in Husserl's phenomenology. Then we look at choice sequences and their logic. Finally, we investigate the differences between Brouwer and Weyl, and argue that Weyl's conception of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Infinity and a Critical View of Logic.Charles Parsons - 2015 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 58 (1):1-19.
    The paper explores the view that in mathematics, in particular where the infinite is involved, the application of classical logic to statements involving the infinite cannot be taken for granted. L. E. J. Brouwer’s well-known rejection of classical logic is sketched, and the views of David Hilbert and especially Hermann Weyl, both of whom used classical logic in their mathematical practice, are explored. We inquire whether arguments for a critical view can be found that are independent of constructivist premises and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • (1 other version)Brouwer and Weyl: The Phenomenology and Mathematics of the Intuitive Continuum.Mark van Atten, Dirk van Dalen & Richard Tieszen - 2002 - Philosophia Mathematica 10 (2):203-226.
    Brouwer and Weyl recognized that the intuitive continuum requires a mathematical analysis of a kind that set theory is not able to provide. As an alternative, Brouwer introduced choice sequences. We first describe the features of the intuitive continuum that prompted this development, focusing in particular on the flow of internal time as described in Husserl's phenomenology. Then we look at choice sequences and their logic. Finally, we investigate the differences between Brouwer and Weyl, and argue that Weyl's conception of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The Iterative Conception of Set: a (Bi-)Modal Axiomatisation.J. P. Studd - 2013 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 42 (5):1-29.
    The use of tensed language and the metaphor of set ‘formation’ found in informal descriptions of the iterative conception of set are seldom taken at all seriously. Both are eliminated in the nonmodal stage theories that formalise this account. To avoid the paradoxes, such accounts deny the Maximality thesis, the compelling thesis that any sets can form a set. This paper seeks to save the Maximality thesis by taking the tense more seriously than has been customary (although not literally). A (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • The Problem of Absolute Universality.Charles Parsons - 2006 - In Agustín Rayo & Gabriel Uzquiano (eds.), Absolute generality. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 203--19.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • (1 other version)Brouwer and Weyl: The phenomenology and mathematics of the intuitive continuumt.Mark van Atten, Dirk van Dalen & Richard Tieszen - 2002 - Philosophia Mathematica 10 (2):203-226.
    Brouwer and Weyl recognized that the intuitive continuum requires a mathematical analysis of a kind that set theory is not able to provide. As an alternative, Brouwer introduced choice sequences. We first describe the features of the intuitive continuum that prompted this development, focusing in particular on the flow of internal time as described in Husserl's phenomenology. Then we look at choice sequences and their logic. Finally, we investigate the differences between Brouwer and Weyl, and argue that Weyl's conception of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • (1 other version)Hermann Weyl's intuitionistic mathematics.Dirk van Dalen - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (2):145-169.
    Dedicated to Dana Scott on his sixtieth birthday.It is common knowledge that for a short while Hermann Weyl joined Brouwer in his pursuit of a revision of mathematics according to intuitionistic principles. There is, however, little in the literature that sheds light on Weyl's role and in particular on Brouwer's reaction to Weyl's allegiance to the cause of intuitionism. This short episode certainly raises a number of questions: what made Weyl give up his own program, spelled out in “Das Kontinuum”, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Das Kontinuum.H. Weyl - 1960 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 25 (3):282-284.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  • Eine Grenze Für die Beweisbarkeit der Transfiniten Induktion in der Verzweigten Typenlogik.Kurt Schütte - 1964 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 7 (1-2):45-60.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations